• Free AI Essay Writer
  • AI Outline Generator
  • AI Paragraph Generator
  • Paragraph Expander
  • Essay Expander
  • Literature Review Generator
  • Research Paper Generator
  • Thesis Generator
  • Paraphrasing tool
  • AI Rewording Tool
  • AI Sentence Rewriter
  • AI Rephraser
  • AI Paragraph Rewriter
  • Summarizing Tool
  • AI Content Shortener
  • Plagiarism Checker
  • AI Detector
  • AI Essay Checker
  • Citation Generator
  • Reference Finder
  • Book Citation Generator
  • Legal Citation Generator
  • Journal Citation Generator
  • Reference Citation Generator
  • Scientific Citation Generator
  • Source Citation Generator
  • Website Citation Generator
  • URL Citation Generator
  • AI Writing Guides
  • AI Detection Guides
  • Citation Guides
  • Grammar Guides
  • Paraphrasing Guides
  • Plagiarism Guides
  • Summary Writing Guides
  • STEM Guides
  • Humanities Guides
  • Language Learning Guides
  • Coding Guides
  • Top Lists and Recommendations
  • AI Detectors
  • AI Writing Services
  • Coding Homework Help
  • Citation Generators
  • Essay Writing Websites
  • Language Learning Websites
  • Math Solvers
  • Paraphrasers
  • Plagiarism Checkers
  • Reference Finders
  • Spell Checkers
  • Summarizers
  • Tutoring Websites

Most Popular

Cognition’s new ai tool devin is set to revolutionize coding industry, do you use quotation marks when paraphrasing, heated discussions erupt on reddit over chatgpt’s entry in scholarly publication.

13 days ago

How to Make Chat GPT Rewrite Text?

Atozmath review, should the law enforce morality essay sample, example.

Admin

Should the law enforce morality?

The question above is one which easily divides potential respondents, for it appears prima facie to the layperson that there is indeed an obvious link between the two concepts, or indeed that they should not in practice be seen as two distinct things. There are those who would disagree of course, and suggest that the law should not invade private life. I aim to discuss this question, by considering R v Brown as a test case, and the thoughts of (Hart and) Devlin, and supplement this with my thoughts on the views of some authors such as Ashworth and Dworkin. Thereafter, I will be able to reasonably conclude that the question is in fact unanswerable, not because the arguments on both sides are balanced, but because the question is meaningless.

I will begin by looking at the R v Brown case, where five males were convicted in court for having performed violent sexual acts in private with the full consent of the so-called victims. What is going on here is that the participants have engaged in acts that are acceptable on their own moral codes (since consent was given), but the state is attempting to enforce some other code.

Lord Templeman suggested that the issue of consent was irrelevant to the question of the illegality of an action, since the latter constitutes a breach of the peace. This traces back to high-minded English snobbery about a king needing able-bodied soldiers. The idea seems to be that a society is more important than its individuals. But this is, of course, erroneous, for it seems obvious, upon reflection, that there can be nothing more sacred than individual liberty.

Ashworth suggests (2009, p.23ff) that we are morally responsible because of said individual autonomy. But this seems contrary to reality; indeed, it is precisely for the benefit of autonomy that we ought not have responsibilities. States are robber bands enlarged, for there is no justice in controlling others; punishment is a cruel and demeaning act which would itself be illegal, were it not for the special legal status the state gives its own actions.

I deem punishment to be immoral, thus, the law does not enforce my morality. Since the consent, and hence, the subjective moralities, of those concerned did not change the law’s position on their acts, the law and morality cannot be linked.

To show this further: Lord Jauncey points out that consent was fully and freely given, and that no one complained to the police at any time, adding that the act occurred in private, and so breached no peace. Despite this, he decides that the act should be punished because it just is illegal. He uses precedents rather than his own reasoning, and adds the charge that was famously imposed on Socrates: the corruption of youth, since members of the group were recruited aged 15. Of course, in order to think youth were corrupted, you must have already thought these acts were morally wrong and so this charge is invalid.

Next, Lord Lowry decides the behavior in question should not be allowed, since it does not further family life. Perhaps here instead we should use something along the lines of what Kell suggests, i.e., disutility: do not make it legal only if it is beneficial, instead, only make it illegal if it is harmful (1994, p. 128).

Lord Mustill (and Lord Slynn agrees with him) begins by revealing that one of the charges was ‘keeping a disorderly house.’ That this is illegal is strange. For it would follow, then, that living in a sort of commune with multiple lovers would also be illegal, and if this is the case, then the law is invading personal moral life, and so is not connected to it. He explains what is really happening in the case. These men cannot be punished for a sexual offence, so the acts are being construed as an assault so they can be punished.

After almost four complete speeches, the idea is put forth that this case should be considered by itself, apart from precedents. He suggests that this private act falls within private morality, and that the law has no business interfering in the same. As for the corruption of youth: for any act that is not in itself illegal, it cannot be illegal to encourage others to perform it.

Having looked through the case and made some observations, I am able to offer a pre-conclusion: the state should not interfere in the lives of its citizens as a result of some action, the doing of which is deemed to be unpleasant or immoral on someone’s moral code, unless that action is actually illegal according to the current laws. D. Archard says it is being true that X should be illegal should not to necessarily follow from X being immoral (1998, p. 99). This is indicative of a divide between the two aspects.

Next, it seems appropriate to look towards the Hart/Devlin debate. Patrick Devlin thinks morality simply should not be separated from legality (1977, p.4). But this does not make any sense. Morality is the internal sense of right and wrong peculiar to the individual; a result of teaching, upbringing, indoctrination, evolution even, and the human condition itself. It cannot then, link with religion, a legal system, or any such code, or it would not be morality at all, for when at once you are following a rule laid down before you, or are performing action X because you have been told either to X or not to not-X, then you are not doing the good action required for your act to be a moral one. Morality must be purely internal to the self, and in some sense arbitrary. It is an entirely subjective thing. Laws are in fact nothing more than the state attempting to stop individuals from practicing their own morality.

Devlin (1997, p. 6) suggests laws exist for the protection of the individual. But what protection is this that does not allow me to consent to certain acts I freely would choose to perform? This is control, not protection. He discusses about enforcing principles a society wishes to enforce, but this is merely a tyranny of the majority in some sense; worse, it is a tyranny of a no-longer-existing majority, since, in most cases, laws are remnants of a harsh conservative past.

Devlin tries to consider private morality (1997, p.8), but fails almost at the beginning. He appears to think private morality is thought to be the right to act immorally in private. But this cannot make sense unless he is imposing an objective morality onto our actions, and so where flees our private morality, brought to light only to be at once set upon and extinguished by someone else’s moral code?

He tries to claim that a fixed, established, and shared morality is as necessary to a society as good governance (1997, p. 13). This seems odd, since the government is the very thing that prevents freedom of moral expression in a society. I can safely say that I do not want good government or fixed morality.

Devlin would next have us believe that there can be no private immoral acts, just as there can be no private treason (1997, p. 13-14). Sadly, he does not realize that it is not allowed that he define morality as shared societal values, and then suggest we cannot have private immoral acts. Of course we cannot, not if morality is defined in terms of society. Whether we can act immorally or not will come up later. Similarly, as Hart comments (1997, 84-6), he thinks removing shared morality will fell his society, but this is only because he defines a society as a group of people who share a particular moral code. Moreover, the parallel between treason and immorality seems altogether unfounded (Hart, 1997, p. 86).

Devlin suggests moral judgement is what any reasonable group of people would be unanimous about. But this seems to involve morality linking with rationality. But this is not so, since morality excludes rationality. It is rational to protect the self, to further the interests of the same. It is considered a good deed in the moral codes of many to perform acts that benefit others more than oneself. So there is no necessary connection between morality and rationality.

Furthermore, were it to be the case that everyone’s moral codes were in agreement that furthering one’s own aims was the moral and right thing to do, this would be entirely contingent and not indicative of a link between morality and rationality.

Devlin (1997, p. 17) admits that our merely disliking X is insufficient for X being illegal; he thinks a further thing is required: viz., we must be disgusted by X. But what line of inquiry is this, where we try to link a fixed, uniform, rigid, objective thing, es decir, the law, with morality on the grounds that the latter is something which is wont to be affected by emotions and whims, and so is something which bears no likeness to the law?

All Devlin is doing in this work is laying out his own personal moral code and then saying that everyone ought to follow it, or, at least, he is saying there exists some pre-made moral code we must all follow. He mistakes morality for something objective and factual (1997, p.23), which it is only insofar as what fact relates subjectively to us as individuals. We each have a fixed deontological moral code; there is objectivity within the framework of subjectivity.

As a general response to Devlin’s ideas, H.L.A. Hart says we used to burn witches because we felt that witchcraft was intolerable (1997, p. 87). Public opinion went in for this sort of thing very strongly; we really were disgusted by the immoral acts of witchcraft. Devlin’s theory would require us to punish witches with the truncheon that is the law. This is intended as a reductio ad absurdum, and shows the problems that arise if we try to connect legality with emotion or morality.

R. Dworkin does something rather novel and considers that, rather than being immoral, something could be from a different moral code (1977, p. 995). This, of course, makes perfect sense, and is what I have said already. I would even go so far as to suggest that it is impossible to act immorally. This is another reason morality and legality must remain separate, because, whereas illegal acts exist, immoral ones do not. Socrates said that no one voluntarily does bad things, and this is true. When people think they have done wrong, they really think that they have done wrong according to someone else’s code, or according to law, but it is in fact impossible for someone to act immorally on their own code. When one supposes one has broken one’s own moral code, what has actually occurred is not the breaking of said code, but a misunderstanding of what the code actually was. It may be said that the wrong-doing is that a law has been violated, and not the actual act performed per se. But this is to give some undue authority to the law, a demon the desire of which it is to enslave us.

We have seen from R v Brown that it is unfair to suggest the law enforce morality, because this would just be some arbitrary morality in which we do not all share, given the entirely subjective nature of morality. We noted a striking divide between the concepts of “morality” and “legality.” We then also realized that morality per se actually excludes any links with a rule-based system or with authority. Finally, we appreciated that it is not possible in reality to act immorally. So, the question “Should the law enforce morality?” is actually meaningless, since the concepts are mutually exclusive, and because, given that we cannot act immorally, there would be nothing to enforce.

Bibliography of Works Consulted

  • Archard, D., 1998, Sexual Consent, Oxford: Westview Press.
  • Ashworth, A. J., 2009, Principles of Criminal Law (6th edition), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Devlin, P., 1977, ‘Morals and the Criminal Law,’ in: Dworkin, R., (ed.),
  • The Philosophy of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 66-82
  • Dworkin, R., 1977, Taking Rights Seriously, London: Duckworth.
  • Feinberg, J., 1984, Harm to Others, Vol 1 of his The Moral Limits of Criminal Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Giles, M., 1994, ‘R v Brown: Consensual Harm and the Public Interest,’ in: Modern Law Review 75, p. 101-111.
  • Hart, H.L.A., 1977, ‘Immorality and Treason,’ in: Dworkin, R., (ed.), The Philosophy of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 83-88.
  • Kell, D., 1994, ‘Social Disutility and the Law of Consent,’ in: Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 14, p. 121-135.
  • R v Brown [1993], All England Law Reports 75.

Follow us on Reddit for more insights and updates.

Comments (0)

Welcome to A*Help comments!

We’re all about debate and discussion at A*Help.

We value the diverse opinions of users, so you may find points of view that you don’t agree with. And that’s cool. However, there are certain things we’re not OK with: attempts to manipulate our data in any way, for example, or the posting of discriminative, offensive, hateful, or disparaging material.

Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

More from Analytical Essay Examples and Samples 2024

Hirschi's Social Bond Theory

Nov 28 2023

Hirschi’s Social Bond Theory

Another Brick In The Wall Meaning

Nov 27 2023

Another Brick In The Wall Meaning

Themes in The Crucible

Themes in The Crucible

Related writing guides, writing an analysis essay.

Remember Me

What is your profession ? Student Teacher Writer Other

Forgotten Password?

Username or Email

  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

The authority of law: Essays on law and morality

The authority of law: Essays on law and morality

  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This revised edition of one of the classic works of modern legal philosophy, first published in 1979, represents the author's contribution which has had an enduring influence on philosophical work on the nature of law and its relation to morality. The new edition includes two previously uncollected essays and a new introduction from the author.

Signed in as

Institutional accounts.

  • GoogleCrawler [DO NOT DELETE]
  • Google Scholar Indexing

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code

Institutional access

  • Sign in with a library card Sign in with username/password Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Sign in through your institution

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Sign in with a library card

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

the law should enforce morality essay

  •   Home

feed

Welcome to the   Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. This repository provides open, global access to the scholarship of Yale Law School faculty and jornals, as well as a selection of unique collections. 

Communities in Yale Law School Open Scholarship Repository

Select a community to browse its collections.

Recently Added

Thumbnail

Sentence Modification in Connecticut: A Guide for Those Navigating the 53a-39 Process

Thumbnail

Constraining and Licensing Arbitrariness: The Stakes in Debates about Substantive-Procedural Due Process

Thumbnail

Valuing ESG

Thumbnail

An Empirical Investigation of Arbitrator Race and Gender in U.S. Arbitration

Thumbnail

Sex/Gender Segregation: A Human Rights Violation, Not a Protection

Export search results.

The export option will allow you to export the current search results of the entered query to a file. Different formats are available for download. To export the items, click on the button corresponding with the preferred download format.

By default, clicking on the export buttons will result in a download of the allowed maximum amount of items.

To select a subset of the search results, click "Selective Export" button and make a selection of the items you want to export. The amount of items that can be exported at once is similarly restricted as the full export.

After making a selection, click one of the export format buttons. The amount of items that will be exported is indicated in the bubble next to export format.

Does Law Exist to Provide Moral Order?

Is social cohesion possible in plural societies? Philosopher H. L. A. Hart weighed in amid debates on abortion and same-sex relationships.

Vintage engraving of The Bench, by William Hogarth. 1758, depicts four judges listening to a case in the Court of Common Pleas.

In 1959, as a response to what was commonly known as the Wolfenden Report, Lord Devlin, an English judge, delivered the Maccabaean Lecture in Jurisprudence at the British Academy. The lecture that would later be published as The Enforcement of Morals . The Wolfenden Report was more correctly called the Report of the Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution. Two years before Devlin’s lecture, the Committee had recommended by a majority of 12 to 1 that, in Britain, “homosexual behaviour between consenting adults in private should no longer be a crime.” Devlin’s objections to this recommendation would spark a passionate public debate between himself and H. L. A. Hart, Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford University.

JSTOR Daily Membership Ad

In his lecture, Devlin countered the Wolfenden Report, arguing that law should both be and is used “ to achieve uniformity ” in society. He went further, stating that the laws against homosexuality were there because the strong feeling of “disgust” was “deeply felt” in society. The presence of disgust, he claimed, “is a good indication that the bounds of [tolerance] are being reached… No society can do without intolerance, indignation and disgust; they are the forces behind the moral law.”

“It is generally accepted,” he continued, “that some shared morality… is an essential element in the constitution of any society. Without it there would be no [social] cohesion.”

Weekly Newsletter

Get your fix of JSTOR Daily’s best stories in your inbox each Thursday.

Privacy Policy   Contact Us You may unsubscribe at any time by clicking on the provided link on any marketing message.

After Lord Devlin’s lecture, Hart, who described himself privately in letters to friends as a “suppressed homosexual,” felt compelled to speak out on BBC radio. As he would state in an interview in later life, he had felt obligated to act because, as he put it: “I think Devlin’s arguments are really bad and misleading and enable reactionary people to claim a philosophical mantle.”

Hart, in his response to Devlin, agreed with the Wolfenden Report’s statement that “there must remain a realm of private morality or immorality which is, in brief and crude terms, not the law’s business.” This idea, Hart argued, had a close connection to John Stuart Mill’s doctrine in his essay On Liberty that stated, “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community against his will is to prevent harm to others.”

Hart was a legal positivist, meaning that he took a social scientific approach to the law, regarding the law as a social fact. What the law is, he argued, and what it ought to be are two distinct questions. As he would argue in his famous The Concept of Law , morality may influence the law, but laws and morals are distinct social phenomena.

In what would become known as Hart’s “separability thesis,” he argued that a law such as the one as obligates a person drive on the right-hand side of the road might be a good law, but it is not a moral principle. One would never go to Britain and say, my morality commands me to drive on the right, and I feel morally compromised driving on the left. Morality can, he argued, influence the law, but it is not synonymous with the law. On the other hand, laws against dangerous driving (or, say, murder), for example, are no doubt influenced by morality, but they are also part of social-bureaucratic order. And well-ordered states are not necessarily moral states. Devlin’s claim that laws are there to enforce morality was, Hart pointed out, simply factually incorrect.

But the problem Hart had with Devlin’s argument were deeper than Mill’s doctrine and his separation of law and morality. Hart was also, along with his great friend Isaiah Berlin, one of the most important twentieth century liberal philosophers who believed in an open, free, democratic, and plural society. Within these societies, both Hart and Berlin argued, are differing moral codes and beliefs. Berlin articulated what was a constant theme in Hart’s writings: that moral principles are incommensurate and often come into direct conflict with one another. One example of this conflict can been in the debate around abortion: pro-life and pro-choice (among others) are conflicting positions, but they both come from a recognizable moral framework.

La Justice by Eustache Le Sueur

To this problem, both philosophers suggested that an open, tolerant, and democratic society was the only moral solution (ironically). “Plural moralities in the conditions of modern large scale societies,” Hart wrote, “might perfectly well be mutually tolerant.” And in fact, “there actually are divergent moralities living in peace” in almost all open democratic societies .

For social cohesion to exist in a society, Hart argued, there is no need for the law to impose a singular “seamless web” of morality over its people, as Devlin had claimed. In fact, to live in a state of freedom, we must be allowed to choose our own moral systems. The law should not impose one way of life on people, a way of life that denies them perfectly harmless and consensual actions in private. As Hart argued in his Liberty, Law and Morality , the private sphere is neither the law’s business, nor society’s.

When asked in an interview if he saw Devlin as threatening liberalization, Hart answered:

He was. Although paradoxically I got to know him and quite liked him… After he produced his arguments against me and Mill, he then wrote a letter to The Times saying he thought the law [on homosexuality] ought to be altered.

In many ways Devlin’s letter was one of the success stories of the liberalization process in mid-twentieth century Britain. Like his friend Isaiah Berlin, Hart was never afraid to discuss issues openly with those who held divergent views. And Devlin’s letter is a testament to just how open and engaged dialogue (and even friendship) can be a persuasive force in society.

It was in this spirit that Hart addressed the issue of abortion in several lectures. For Hart, moral pluralism meant that there was nothing necessarily wrong with a society that contained within it divergent views on the morality of abortion. As he said in the interview mentioned above, “I can see how Catholics might object to abortion.” His legal positivist beliefs did not allow him into any obfuscation of facts. As he openly acknowledged , medical facts confirm that “the physical structure… of a foetus is remarkably similar to that of a new born baby” and “the legal facts are those which show that the law recognises the unborn foetus as having rights.”

He would also go on to caution those who dismiss out of hand that the “foetus is at any stage a person,” suggesting that this position had led to a failure to convert “many to a different view of the moral status of the foetus.” But, he pointed out, “only rarely has English law equated any form of abortion with murder.” Hart’s point was that, in England, some traditional belief, that can be seen in the law’s formulation, held that there was some distinction between a foetus and a new-born baby.

He also pointed out that what is now commonly called a “pro-choice position” is most often held by people who do not disregard the sanctity of human life. “Many of those who have campaigned for the relaxation of [the abortion] law,” he pointed out, are quite often “opponents of capital punishment and pacifists.” As he went on, “similarly, at the national level, the Scandinavian countries who have been the foremost and most consistent supporters of liberalisation of the law were also among the earliest to abandon capital punishment.”

Hart believed that a free society should allow for morally autonomous choice on matters such as homosexuality and abortion. But all laws, he believed, should be scrutinized for what harm they might cause. Hart in this pursuit addressed the issue of the harm that the abortion laws produced in Britain before their liberalization in 1967. In 1950s and 60s, it was thought that around 10,000 illegal abortions took place in Britain per annum. This meant that, in 26 years, 260,000 women from all walks of life were guilty of a crime punishable by a prison sentence. But when Hart looked at the statistics, he discovered that there were only around 55 convictions each year. This, to Hart, suggested that the society had little interest in upholding this law, and that it had become a dead letter. He also pointed out that illegal abortion was part of a “high profit criminal industry,” which offered “targets for the blackmailer and corrupting temptations to law enforcement agencies.”

As he discussed this issue in front of an Australian audience in 1971, he pointed out that relaxation of abortion laws in Britain were at least in part helping to solve the problem of “unwanted children, particularly illegitimate children, the reduction of maternal mortality through illegal abortion, and the reduction of illegal abortion.”

Hart would not allow himself to disregard the negative impact of liberalization. There had been, he observed, “the growth of a vast private sector where often very high fees are charged and large profits may be made by doctors.” This industry was bound to compound unwanted inequality in society, creating one “abortion law for the rich and another for the poor.” He also had “not the slightest doubt that a large scale racket has developed in this sector.” Doctors were making significant amounts of money at the expense of the unhappiness of women.

Abortion law reform, Hart would go on to say, was not like the relaxation of the law against homosexuality. It had deeply significant social impacts that must be addressed by government. It required “careful planning of available resources” and “should be accompanied, and if possible preceded by a really effective provision of free contraceptive services and education in their use.”

Consistent with his separability thesis, Hart’s philosophical positions were always accompanied by strong moral convictions. As he would argue, laws “must in the end be submitted to a moral scrutiny.” And in this regard, the liberalization of abortion laws had made it “possible for large numbers of pregnant women who do not wish to continue their pregnancy to lay their case frankly before doctors and to discuss it without shame and without fear.”

In the 1960s, liberal legislation pushed through parliament, and England witnessed the likes of the conservative Lord Devlin softening his position. But as the reactionary movements of the 1980s took hold, a handbrake to liberalization was applied: Margaret Thatcher would do her level best to place the liberalization vehicle into reverse. In 1988, her government pushed through “a new law to reduce the legal limit for abortions… from 28 weeks of pregnancy to 18.” Some months later, her government would pass a law that “prohibited local authorities and schools from ‘promoting’ homosexuality.”

Interviewer David Sugarman asked Hart in 1988, “What do you think about the current tendencies to reverse liberalization of the 60s in terms of abortion, homosexuality, and so?” Hart responded emphatically, “I loathe it.”

Support JSTOR Daily! Join our new membership program on Patreon today.

JSTOR logo

JSTOR is a digital library for scholars, researchers, and students. JSTOR Daily readers can access the original research behind our articles for free on JSTOR.

Get Our Newsletter

More stories.

https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Benedictus_Spinoza._Line_engraving_by_W._Pobuda_after_(A._P._Wellcome_V0005578.jpg

Nice Guy Spinoza Finishes…First?

Police find bog body dated over 2,000 years in Bellaghy. Police Service of Northern Ireland

A Body in the Bog

Jamia Mosque in Nairobi

A Mughal Mosque in Kenya

illustration of a woman's body on abstract blob background

Do You Own Your Body?

Recent posts.

  • Prisoners’ Pastimes
  • The Accordion Blues
  • The International History of “Indigenous” Malay Healers
  • Turkish Cats, Crow Pie, and AI DJs
  • The Swooning Knights of Medieval Stories

Support JSTOR Daily

Sign up for our weekly newsletter.

McGill Law Journal

The Legal Enforcement of Morals and the So-Called Hart-Devlin Controversy

Table of Contents

The Legal Enforcement of Morals and the

So-Called Hart-Devlin Controversy

Yves Caron *

The enforcement of morals through legal sanctions is not a new topic to legal philosophers. It has, in the past decade, been the object of a new and thorough examination, though it is still open to further discussion. The “new morality” of the second half of the twentieth century will also contribute to keep the fire alive as a result of the widening gap between the traditional Christian morality and the morals that modern society seems increasingly prepared to accept and tolerate.

Morality implies a basic reference to the distinction of what is right from what is wrong. Various moralities differ as to the extent of what is right and what is wrong, or good and bad, and therefore, each community, nation or society may have its own morality, according to the local beliefs, whether social, political, religious or other. Moreover, the expressions “morals” and “morality”, though broad in meaning, have too often been understood to have a close connexion with sexual morality. Legal and philosophical writers are not always careful to indicate that although the main illustrations of moral problems are generally taken from sexual morality, morality remains fundamentally a classification of what is right and wrong. More sophisticated definitions of morality have also been worked out in the debate on the distinction between law and morals. Following the utilitarians of the last century,’ Professor H.L.A. Hart proposes two working definitions of morality: 2 “positive morality”, or the morality actually accepted and shared by a given social group, and “critical morality”, which may be defined as “the general moral principles used in the criticism of actual social institutions including positive morality”. Hart then proceeds to examine the question of

* D. Phil. (Oxon), Associate Professor, Faculty of Law, McGill University. ‘Austin, J., The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, (London, 1954), ed.

by Hart, pp. 11-12, 125427.

2 Hart, H.L.A., Law, Liberty and Morality, (1263), Vintage Book ed., p. 20,

hereinafter cited as Hart.

McGILL LAW JOURNAL

the legal enforcement of morals as one of “critical morality about the legal enforcement of positive morality”. 3

term “enforcement” also needs some clarification. The legal enforcement of morals means, in practice, the separation of crimes from sins. There are two main instruments to ensure the enforcement of morals: statutory legislation and judge-made law. When the legislator adopts a statute regulating some aspect of morality, the enforcement of morals is seen as a matter of policy at the political level: no government is likely to adopt a law that does not satisfy the moral conscience of the population. The actual enforcement of such a law can also be a matter of policy, either political or merely administrative. But when the legislator remains silent on some aspects of the legal enforcement of morals, the courts have often stepped in, and reaffirmed their right and duty as custos morum of the people. In those cases, the legal enforcement of morals is not a matter of political policy but of mere interpretation of what is right and wrong, as assessed by expert witnesses and stated by a jury, subject to the revision of the higher courts. Their judgement and opinion will, therefore, constitute the yardstick that will be used to measure what society is or will be prepared to tolerate in the field of morality, and to what extent it is prepared to accept the legal enforcement of morals.

But why should society care for the legal enforcement of morals in the first place? Is the right to punish or to impose sanctions an essential or natural right of society? What is the purpose of punishment, and, in any event, does punishment yield sufficiently good results to warrant its use and that of the legal apparatus needed to administer it? In some instances, as it will be shown, the legal enforcement of morals is a farce, and sometimes a nuisance, because certain crimes are undetectable and certain prohibitions are simply unenforceable. It would, therefore, seem right to say that however necessary it is to legally enforce some aspects of morality, if the law cannot supply the appropriate weapons, it is better to leave the area unregulated rather than to adopt unenforceable rules. But let us face the question as a whole, and see how the problems of legal enforcement of morals actually arise.

The recent years have provided legal philosophers with many good cases and problems concerning the legal enforcement of morals: the most famous are the Wolfenden Report 4 and the Ladies’ Directory

3 Those definitions are further considered infra, at pp. 27 ff. 4 Report of the Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution, Cmnd.

247, (London, 1957).

THE SO-CALLED HART-DEVLIN CONTROVERSY

case r (also herein referred to as the Shaw case), which have been used as guideposts in the debate, and have been widely publicized.

However, as an illustration of the fact that this question is far from settled, a freshly rendered judgment of the Supreme Court of Canada in the case of Klippert v. The Queen 6 will be used as the starting point of the present analysis. It shows how, just when the Parliament of the United Kingdom was acting upon the Wolfenden Committee’s recommendations after ten years by repealing the criminal prohibition against homosexual acts between consenting adults in private, the Supreme Court of Canada affirmed a judgment which not only applied the Criminal Code of Canada concerning homosexual acts, but also interpreted its terms so as to include in the category of “dangerous sexual offenders.’ 7 homosexuals Consequently, it sentenced the accused to preventive detention that could last for life.

Klippert v. The Queen

The facts of the case were very simple. The defendant, Klippert, was not caught in an indecent act, but had told the police, while being questioned about some other matter, that he had been a homosexual for twenty-four years. He was subsequently convicted on four charges of gross indecency involving homosexual acts with four different persons. His first sentence of three years was later replaced by a sentence of indefinite (preventive) detention. At no point was there any suggestion of violence or offences against children, or offenses committed in public, though the defendant admitted being a homosexual for so many years. All convictions against him stemmed from private acts with consenting adult males.8 The argument before the Supreme Court of Canada centered around the definition of a “dangerous sexual offender” in the Criminal Code of Canada, as a result of which the preventive detention sentence could be administered. The final decision was

5Shaw V. Director of Public Prosecution, [1962] A.C. 220 (H.L.);

[1961] 2 All E.R. 446 (Ii.L.); [1961] 1 All E.R. 330 (C.A.), sub nomine, 1egina v. Shaw; see also the recent obscenity and pornography cases in the U.S.A.: Roth V. United States, (1966), 354 U.S. 413; Memoirs v. Massachusetts, (1966), 383 U.S. 413; Ginzburg v. U.S., (1966), 383 U.S. 463; Mishkin v. New York, (1966), 383 U.S. 502; Magrath, C.P., The Obscenity Cases: Grapes of Roth, [1,966] The Supreme Court Review, 7; Elias, E.A., Sex Publications and Moral Corruption: The Supreme Court Dilemma, (1967), 9 William & Mary L. Rev. 302.

GKlippert v. The Queen, [1967] S.C.R. 822. 7S. 659 (b) Cr. C. 8 See the medical evidence, cited by Cartwright, J., at pp. 827-828.

reached by a majority of the Court (three to two), based on an interpretation of the terms “dangerous sexual offender”. The Code provides that the provision is aimed at persons who constitute a “danger to others”, but the majority found that the Code’s reference to further sexual offences 9 that might be committed by a previously convicted person was an “alternative element” to that of the danger of injury to others. Mr. Justice Fauteux, speaking for the majority, said:

With deference, I cannot either agree with the view that the intent and object of the provisions dealing with dangerous sexual offenders, is solely to protect persons from becoming the victims of those whose failure to control their sexual impulses renders them a source of danger and that to apply the definition to a person, who is not to be a source of danger, would give the definition an effect inconsistent with the intent or object of these provisions. 10 On the other hand, the two dissenting judges found that the Code’s reference to further sexual offences must read as relating to danger to others; otherwise, it would be tantamount to saying that a person who is not dangerous must nevertheless be regarded as dangerous:

It would be with reluctance and regret that I would have found myself compelled by the words used to impute to Parliament the intention of enacting that the words ‘dangerous sexual offender’ shall include in their meaning ‘a sexual offender who is not dangerous’. 11 Cartwright, J., dissenting, cites lengthy extracts from the medical and psychiatric evidence, showing that doctors had agreed that “there was no danger of the appellant using violence of any sort or attempt- ing coercion of anyone”, though they did foresee “the likelihood of the appellant committing further acts of gross indecency with other consenting adult males”. 12

9 Canadian Criminal Code: “s. 569 (b): ‘dangerous sexual offender’ means a person who, (i) by his own conduct in any sexual matter, has shown a failure to control his sexual impulses, and (ii) who (a) is likely to cause injury, pain or other evil to any person, through failure in the future to control his sexual impulses or (b) is dikely to commit a further sexual offence …. ” S. 661 (3): “Where the court finds that the accused is a dangerous sexual offender it shall, notwithstanding anything in this Act or any other Act of the Parliament of Canada, impose upon the accused a sentence of preventive detention in lieu of any other sentence that might be imposed for the offence of which he was con- victed or that was imposed for such offence, or in addition to any sentence that was imposed for such offence if the sentence has expired.”

‘ Fauteux, J., at pp. 834-835. 11 Cartwright, J., at p. 831. 12 At p. 829. Maxwell on Interpretation of Statutes, 11th ed., at pp. 58-59, is also cited in support of the dissenting judges’ interpretation of the Criminal Code; see Cartwright, J., at p. 830.

The result, however, is that a homosexual is not only regarded as a criminal by the Canadian Criminal Code, but also treated as a dangerous sexual offender, and is being incarcerated for life as if he constituted a danger to others and had no control over his sexual impulses, although he was convicted for acts committed with con- senting adults in private.13

One might say that the decision is a result of a narrow and literal interpretation of the Criminal Code. Cries of “dark-ages dungeon”, “ridiculous justice” and others have been heard in the House of Commons as a result of the Court’s decision. Reference was made to the Wolfenden Report and the new Act on sexual offences in the United Kingdom,14 but the majority was left unmoved by such precedents, in a case where it could have rendered a more lenient interpretation of the Criminal Code.

Whether the criminal law, with respect to sexual misconduct of the sort in which appellant has indulged for nearly twenty-five years, should be changed to the extent to which it has been recently in England, by the Sexual Offences Act, 1967 is obviously not for us to say; our jurisdiction is to interpret and apply laws validly enacted.15 Whether the view of the Supreme Court of Canada is that of the majority of the Canadian population (criminal law being a matter of federal jurisdiction in Canada) remains to be seen. A few weeks following the Klippert decision, the Minister of Justice introduced a series of new amendments to the Criminal Code, which would have the effect, inter alia, of making the Canadian law relating to homo- sexual practices identical with the new English Act of 1967,10 and of liberalizing the law relating to abortion. At the time of the writing of this paper, Parliament had not yet studied this Bill, but comments from the press and other organized social, professional and religious groups suggest that the new reform might be the object of stormy debates before it is carried out. – a It will be yet another occasion for

13″If the law on this subject matter is as interpreted by the Courts below, it means that every man in Canada who indulges in sexual misconduct of the sort forbidden by s. 149 of the Criminal Code with another consenting adult male and who appears likely, if at liberty, to continue such misconduct should be sentenced to preventive detention, that is to incarceration for life. However loathsome conduct of the sort mentioned may appear to all normal persons, I think it improbable that Parliament should have intended such a result.” Cart- wright, J., at p. 831.

14 Sexual Offences Act, 1967, c. 60. 15 Fauteux, J., at p. 836. 16 See infra and the Wolfenden Report. Ica The House of Commons has now started the study of the Bill, which has been presented as one and undivided (omnibus) block, and has indeed been the object of stormy and biased debates. Ed.’s note.

Canada to review its common morality and decide whether it is prepared to allow a maximum of freedom to its citizens, or will, as a result of social or religious bias, require that the activities of the individuals, although seemingly of a private character, be investigated and perhaps punished by the arm of the law. The Canadian Parliament has just recently started this review by finally liberalizing the law concerning the death penalty.17 In the meantime, however, the Supreme Court’s decision in the Klippert case remains as an example of extremely stringent policy in the legal enforcement of morals, which was perhaps not clearly foreseen by those who enacted the criminal laws. This will be a good occasion for reshaping the Canadian concepts on the relation between law and morality. This essay purports to suggest some ideas and criticism concerning the legal enforcement of morals.

Report of the (Wolfenden) Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution

The legal enforcement of morals was discussed by the Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution; 18 the actual recommen- dations of the Committee, though relevant here, yield in value to the actual principles upon which they rested. The Committee proceeded to define what it considered was the nature and function of the law. Through extensive examination of witnesses, however, it had to admit that opinions differ so much as to what the law is, or as to what is regarded as offensive, injurious or inimical to the common good, or as to what moral, social or cultural standards are, that it had to adopt standards acceptable to the community in general, though not accepted by many citizens. The Committee has found itself unable to succeed in discovering an “unequivocal public opinion”, although several persons had suggested that there is a direct relation- ship between the law and public opinion. The members had therefore to reach “conclusions for ourselves rather than to base them on what is often transient and seldom precisely ascertainable”.’ 9

The subject matter of morality, whether sexual or not, is not always easily debated, and the conclusion of the Wolfenden Committee reflects such a state of facts: this area is still one where the limits of religious belief, political and social principles and behaviour have not been determined, or at least not fully investigated, and where

17 See infra, n. 92. 18 The Committee was appointed on August 24, 1954, and reported on August

12, 1957; legislation followed in 1967, see, supra, n. 14.

19 Wolfenden Report, para. 16.

the individuals are not prepared to state their views with the know- ledge that their opinion is founded upon ascertained principles or the past, what was good even upon reasonable information. In according to religion was accepted as socially good; but nowadays, since morality and religion have been separated to a greater extent, both philosophers and lawyers experience difficulties in ascertaining the public good (public order) and the general moral sense (common morality).

The Wolfenden Committee adopts the view that laws must be acceptable to the general moral sense (as determined by their own search) ,20 and that laws should not enter the field of “private moral conduct” unless such conduct affects public good. On the other hand, however, the report does not supply a definition of “crime”, or of “public opinion.” To define a crime as “an act which is punished by State” does not answer the question ;21 the notion of “crime”, as distinguished from “sin”, will therefore be based on the purpose and function of the law in the field of morals, that is,

(T)o preserve public order and decency, to protect the citizen from what is offensive or injurious, and to provide sufficient safeguards against exploitation and corruption of others, particularly those who are specially vulnerable because they are young, weak in body or mind, inexperienced, or in a state of special physical, official or economic dependence. 22 The law is the guardian of the public good, and has no function “to intervene in the private lives of citizens, or to seek to enforce any particular pattern of behaviour, further than is necessary to carry out the purposes” of preserving public order.23 This general concept of the law has led the Committee to further distinguish between “public morality” and “private morality” or immorality that is the private life of individuals as such:

There remains one additional counter-argument which we believe to be decisive, namely, the importance which society and the law ought to give to individual freedom of choice and action in matters of private morality. Unless a deliberate attempt is to be made by society. acting through the agency of the law, to equate the sphere of crime with that of sin, there must remain a realm of private morality and immorality which is, in brief and crude terms, not the law’s business. To say this is not to condone or encourage private immorality. On the contrary, to emphasize the personal and private nature of moral or immoral conduct is to emphasize the private

2o Idem. 21 Ibid., para. 13. 22 Idem. 28 Ibid., paras. 14, 52. In a famous quip, The Minister of Justice and now Prime Minister of Canada said that: “The State has no business in the bedrooms of the Nation”.

and personal responsibility of the individual for his own actions, and that is a responsibility which a mature agent can properly be expected to carry for himself without the threat of punishment from the law.24 As a consequence, the Wolfenden Committee recommended, inter alia, “that homosexual behaviour between consenting adults in private should no longer be a criminal offence”, 25 because of the so-called area of private morality. Apart from its own reasons, the Committee cites the Report of the Street Offences Committee,2 which stated that criminal law “is not concerned with private morals or with ethical sanctions”. 27

But whatever the merits of the Wolfenden Report may be, and notwithstanding its appeal to many (the report was finally im- plemented by legislation in 1967), its underlying philosophical reason- ing has not been convincing. The purpose is real; there is a need for reforms in the legal enforcement of morals, but the juris- prudential basis of the report is indeed a weak one. For example, the existence of a so-called distinction between public and private morality or immorality has yet to be demonstrated or even justified. The main feature of morality relates to the distinction between right and wrong; unless the legal enforcement of morals purports to regulate the private lives of individuals, all morality is necessarily public, whether the act is done in private or in public. “Private morality” does not exist; “wrongful” acts done in private relate to “public” morality. The Committee’s position would be indefensible if its main principle was applied to some other fields of morality and of legal enforcement of morals; such crimes as incest between con- senting adults in private, euthanasia or murder voluntarily consented to by the victims, and attempted suicide are examples of “wrongful” (i.e. for the purposes of the debate) acts between consenting adults in private which would fall within the Committee’s notion of private morality. Yet, our legal system has been allowed to intrude into those areas of would be private immorality to bring such acts under the effects of the law. It is not too early to say here that the Wolfenden Committee’s underlying distinction between public and private morality did not lie on proper foundations, and that indeed it constitutes an artificial theory.

On the other hand, it is useful to mention here that the Com- mittee did not believe in the decay of society and civilization as a

24Ibid., para. 61. 25 Ibid., para. 62. 26 Cmd. 3231 (London, 1928). 27 Wolfenden Report, para. 226.

result of a relaxation of morals; an idea which was put forward in the Shaw case and by some legal writers.28

Although the Wolfenden Report was not implemented until more than a decade following its publication, it was obvious that this report, together with the report of the Street Offences Committee, would provide enough substance for lawyers and philosophers, and indeed for the general population, to think about during those past years. The Wolfenden Committee actually predicted the need for a new interpretation of the notion of enforcement of morals as a result of the recommendations. For example, the ban on street-walking resulted in an increase of other means of advertising prostitution. 29 The Ladies’ Directory case came in its place in the evolution of the legal enforcement of morals. However, the outcome of the Shaw case does fit into the pattern suggested by the Wolfenden Committee.

Shaw v. Director of Public Prosecution.”0

It may be said that the decision of the House of Lords in the Shaw case is the ultimate result of a zealous performance by the Director of Public Prosecution. Not long after the adoption of the new Street Offences Act, 1956, Shaw published a Ladies’ Directory which contained not only the names and addresses of prostitutes, but also nude photographs and various notes relating to the repertoire and perverse capabilities of the advertisers. If Shaw had been re- munerating himself by the proceeds from the sale of a magazine containing only the names, addresses and telephone numbers of prostitutes, he would have committed no specific offence; but the directory also contained materials which made it an obscene libel. By taking payment from the prostitutes themselves, Shaw committed the statutory offence of living “wholly or in part on the earnings of prostitution”. 31 As the publisher of the magazine, Shaw was prose- cuted under three separate counts: (a) living on the earnings of to prostitution; (b) publishing obscene materials; corrupt public morals. The last count was very likely added by the Director of Public Prosecution because it was felt that the first two

(c) conspiracy

28 Ibid., para. 54; see infra, Shaw v. D.P.P. 29″Another possible consequence is an increase in small advertisements

in shops or local newspapers, offering the services of ‘masseuses’, ‘models’ or ‘com- panions’; but we think that this would be less injurious than the presence of prostitutes in the streets.” Wolfenden Report, para. 286.

30 Shaw v. D.P.P., [1961] 2 All E.R. 446 (H.L.), (hereinafter referred to also

as: the Ladies’ Directory case or the Shaw case).

B1 Sexual Offences Act, 1956, 4-5 Eliz. 2, c. 69, s. 80(1); Devlin, P., The Enforcement of Morals, (London, 1965), pp. 87-89, hereinafter cited as Devlin; Hart, op. cit., pp. 7 ff.

were weak, and to make sure that the accused could be cornered by a broad interpretation of the law. The final outcome may have been a surprise, however, for Shaw was convicted under all three counts. The main instrument of his conviction was said to be the jury, and many judges were happy to rely upon the jurors’ opinion as being the only solution to this case:

(I) n the case of a charge of conspiracy to corrupt public morals, the uncertainty that necessarily arises from the vagueness of general words can only be resolved by the opinion of twelve chosen men and women. I am content to leave it to them.8 2

This case was commented upon in various reviews and articles, and it is not intended to duplicate those materials. However, it will be useful for our purposes to restate some of its major themes. The Courts, and especially the House of Lords, felt that the creation of new (criminal) offences does not fall within their competence, mainly because the citizens have a right to know in advance what the law is, particularly the criminal law, and what deeds are pro- hibited and punished.

On the other hand, the courts claimed a residual power to enforce the supreme and fundamental purpose of the law, and saw themselves as the custos morum of the state, as they were in the earlier days of the Star Chamber, a power which, so they said, was maintained well after the Chamber had been abolished.33 The courts must there- fore be the guardian of public morals and cannot tolerate those forms of immorality that could lead to the moral decay of society. In the Shaw case, the House of Lords defined the “fundamental purpose of the law” in connexion with the needs of morality; it did not commit itself to drawing a division line between religious and social belief, but in effect took for granted that religious principles and Christian morality were an undivided part of the English society. In order to protect those principles and maintain the social order, the English law has retained such an offence as the conspiracy to corrupt public morals, and it is the duty of the Court to see that the law is obeyed. The majority of the judges did not think it necessary to question the respective limits of “sin” and “crime”;

32 Per Viscount Simonds, [1961] 2 All E.R. 446, at 453. 3 “When Lord Mansfield, speaking long after the Star Chamber had been abolished, said that the Court of King’s Bench was the custos morum of the people and had the superintendency of offences contra bones mores, he was asserting, as I now assert, that there is in that court a residual power, where no statute has yet intervened to supersede the common law, to superintend those offences which are prejudicial to the public welfare.” Per Viscount Simonds, ibid., at p. 452.

they were content with the principle that morality is a part of the social or public order, and that an offence against morals was an attack against society. Therefore, it was only natural to protect society through the legal weapons available, and it was the duty of the Court to act as the guardian of morality and social order. In such cases as that under study, where it was necessary to apply to a given set of facts the vagueness of such broad principles, the judges were happy to leave the interpretation of the terms and the application of the rule of law in the hands of a jury.

The judges seem to have had more concern for the adaptation of the common law offence, namely conspiracy to corrupt public morals, to the present situation. In this instance, the offence did not “consist of the publication” of the directory, but of “an agreement to corrupt public morals by means of the magazines which might never have been published”. 34 They tended to adopt the narrow- minded attitude of the trial judge who sees no other alternative but to apply the law as it stands in the statute book to a clear-cut situation.

Lord Reid, dissenting in the House of Lords, pointed out that the Lords were reversing their own view, and were expanding the very crime of conspiracy after they had ceased to extend offences by individuals.8 5 The Court is in fact creating a new offence by the extension of the doctrine of conspiracy; it must, according to the Court’s reasoning, be a crime today to conspire to seduce a particular man, and the offence cannot be limited to a conspiracy to corrupt public morals.86 Owing to differences in opinions as to how far the law ought to punish immoral acts which are not done in the face of the public, the Court is not the proper place to settle that type of argument. Parliament is the proper authority to deal with such matters, and “where Parliament fears to tread it is not for the courts to rush in”.37

Consequently, it is impossible to agree with the idea that the law is whatever a jury thinks it ought to be. One must query whether society as a whole is affected by the offence or conspiracy, or only those who actually read the publication, or only a limited number of persons among those readers. If there is no possible corruption, there is no conspiracy at all, though conspiracy might have existed without actual corruption if it was technically possible. Lord Reid does not, however, complete his argument by a consideration of the fact that

34 Per Lord Tucker, ibid., at p. 466. 35 Per Lord Reid, ibid., at p. 457. 36 Ibid., at p. 458. 37 Ibid., at p. 457.

prostitution and perverse practices are not prohibited as such; 8 the prohibition affects socially injurious manifestations of such practices as, for instance, streetwalking and bawdy-house keeping. Therefore, it is not a crime to indulge in prostitution, but it is an offence to advertise oneself as a prostitute. One aspect of this case was left undiscussed by the judges: it seems that if the directory had contained only the names and addresses of prostitutes, there would have been no conviction under the third count (or on the second, for that matter). The nature of the document was changed as a result of the addition of photographs and other mentions (not reported or detailed in the Law Reports) (sic) relating to perverse practices and individual specialties. It would then seem that the publication of an ordinary directory would not constitute a con- spiracy to corrupt public morals – no more than the mere fact of prostitution – whereas the publication of obscene photographs and literature would. Fortunately, no one claims that there is any logic to be found in such reasoning.

This case has, obviously, been under severe attacks, mainly because of the stand of the House of Lords in the interpretation of its own function as custos morum, and of the ancient Common law offence of conspiring to corrupt public morals. Critics have noted the small amount of discussion on the boundaries between crime and sin, on the concept of morality and on the contemporary function of the law as a weapon to enforce morals.3 9

The So-Called Hart-Devlin Controversy

Lord Devlin and Professor H.L.A. Hart have exposed their personal views on modern morality and the enforcement of morals in a number of writings. 40 The reader benefits from those essays in many ways, since both writers have had the opportunity of comment-

38With such exceptions as sodomy and bestiality. 39 On the Shaw case, see further: Hart, op. cit., pp. 7 ff.; Hall Williams, J.E., The Ladies’ Directory and Criminal Conspiracy: The Judge as Custos Morum, (1961), 24 Mod. L. Rev. 626; Goodhart, A.L., The Shaw Case, the Law and Public Morals, (1961), 77 L. Q. Rev. 560; Mewett, A.W., Morality and the Criminal Law, (1961-62), 14 U. of T. L. J. 213; Devlin, op. cit., pp. 87 ff.

40 See generally: Devlin, op. cit., pp. 1 ff., 86 ff., 102 ff.; Devlin’s book The Enforcement of Morals includes the original conferences which had previously been published elsewhere; chapters I, V and VI are especially reviewed here; Devlin, P., Law and Morality, (1962-65), 1 Manit. L. S. J. 243; Hart, op. cit.; Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, (1958), 71 Harv. L. Rev. 593; Hart, Social Solidarity and the Enforcement of Morality, (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1; Hart, The Use and Abuse of Criminal Law, (1965), 8 The Lawyer 47.

ing on one another’s comments of one’s own comments. The danger in that type of debate is to enter into a mere battle of words; 41 other commentators have also joined the band-wagon, and at one point the so-called controversy on the enforcement of morals could have turned into a debate similar to the famous corporate personality battle of earlier years.

But after all, is there such a thing as a Hart-Devlin controversy, and if so, is it just a battle of words ? The author takes the view here, after an examination of both propositions, that the prevailing conclusion is that Lord Devlin and Professor Hart, and a few of their followers, do not even speak the same language, and that it is a juridicial and philosophical error to try and reduce to a single concept the premises of a given system. Excessive “labelism” is one of the abuses of contemporary jurisprudence. It is submitted that too much energy has been devoted to the interpretation of the under- lying meaning of the opponents’ words, and too little has been oriented to constructive analysis and to the observation of facts. In this area, however, Lord Devlin would emerge as the best contributor.42

Comparing Hart and Devlin is tantamount to opposing two different systems; their approach to morality, their purpose and even their vocabulary are different. The latter is looking for a modus vivendi, seeing society as a group that needs organization and rules for the behaviour of its members, whereas the former is concerned with the definition of basic principles and the rationalization of the human activity. Moreover, Hart’s primary concern goes to the indi- vidual, whereas Devlin’s preoccupation is for society. Their theories, in the end, are not that far apart; Hart deals with the opposition between law and morality, while Devlin discusses the interplay of law and morality.

Lord Devlin’s series of lectures on the enforcement of morals are based on a general concept of society; society exists as a series of facts, and enjoys the use of several means and weapons to main- tain its existence and improve the standards of living of its mem- bers. It has been said that Lord Devlin does not actually define

41 See inf’a, and Devlin, op. cit., p. 13, n. 1; Devlin, loc. cit., (1962-1965), 1

Manit. L.S.J. 243, at p. 254.

42 In his most recent essay on the legal enforcement of morals ((1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1), Hart proposes a distinction between the ‘classical thesis’, the ‘disintegration thesis’ (attributed to Devlin – of Devlin, pp. 94, 114) and the ‘conservative thesis’ (see Dworkin, Lord Devlin and the Enforcement of Morals, (1965-1966), 75 Yale L.J. 986). It does not appear, however, that this new classification sheds more light on the problems of legal enforcement of morals. It tends to hide the facts behind the men who discuss them and to oversimplify the issues by the uses of words.

“society”, 43 whereas others criticize him for having based his theory on a “confused definition of what society js”,44 id est, the notion of “shared morality”. Both criticisms seem unjustified, because the very concept of “society” is a very difficult one to enclose within a formal definition. There are as many notions of society as there are societies, and notwithstanding those critics, Devlin’s view that a society “is a community of ideas” is sufficient enough for the present pur- poses. 45 Beyond that, Lord Devlin is more inclined to enumerate what may be found in a society than to build up a final definition. 4 In the field of morality, there are some areas in which the law does not interfere, at least not in most western countries. The law leaves religion to the private judgment of individuals, and it is the same with morals.

What went wrong in the Wolfenden Report, as Lord Devlin puts it, is that as a result of an error of jurisprudence, the Committee was looking for a single principle to explain the division between crime and sin; as a consequence, it purported to ensure the protec- tion of the individual instead of that of society. The Committee’s definition of the function of the law is therefore incomplete and misleading.

Although the law does not interfere with religion or morals, our society is a Christian one,47 and as such, it cannot make its own rules without regard to Christian morals. Crimes may be classified into three categories: (a) regulatory offences, such as traffic viola- tions; (b) criminal rules on moral precepts, such as the prohibition of theft or murder; (c) criminal rules which tend to regulate “im- morality as such”, like the laws on prostitution or homosexuality, which have no other apparent justification but the regulation of immorality as such. On the other hand, criminal law has been based on traditional moral principles; for example, the victim’s consent to a crime never constitutes an excuse on behalf of the accused. But there are cases where there is more than a victim’s consent; there can be a victim’s request. A person who wants to commit suicide, for instance, could request the help of another to pull the trigger.

43 E.g. Ison, T. G., The Enforcement of Morals, (1967), 3 U. B. C. L. Rev. 263,

4 4 Hart, op. cit., p. 82; Hart, loo. cit, (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1, at pp. 3-4;

Devlin, op. cit., pp. 9-10; see infra, nn. 45, 46 and the text.

45 Devlin, op. cit., pp. 9, 89. 4 8 Devlin, op. cit.: “Every society has a moral structure as well as a political one.. .”, at p. 9; “Without shared ideas on politics, morals, and ethics no society can exist.”, at p. 10; see infra, and Devlin, p. 13, n. 1.

47 Devlin, generally, chapters I, V and VI.

Similarly, euthanasia, suicide pacts, duelling, abortion, incest or homosexuality can be said to relate more directly to the individual’s morality than to social order; but the law denies the existence of such “private morality” and makes it an offence against public order and common morality to commit any such deed.

Lord Devlin asks three questions, the answers to which will provide the proper rules for governing society and the individuals: (a) has society the right to judge morals? Or, is there such a thing as public morality, or are morals a matter of private judgment? (b) If public morality is found to exist, then has society a weapon to enforce its judgment? (c) If the answer to (b) is yes, then in which cases will the weapon be used ?48

In the examination of the first question, it

is proposed that every society has both a political and a moral structure, which are not to be confused and which have to be protected. Political order calls for one set of rules, moral order for another; any attempt to weaken either should be punished with equal strength, because the very existence of society is at stake.

Moral order should not be taken for religion or other manifes- tations of human behaviour, but it may embody some patterns of behaviour that have been borrowed from religion. For example, marriage in our society is conceived on the very lines of the Chris- tian marriage, not because our society as such is Christian, but because it so happened that the majority that formed our society was Christian, and that it was their thought to base the social order on the same ideals. Therefore, the concept of marriage that is part of our moral order is in essence monogamous, and society has undertaken to protect it as such, because an attack against marriage would constitute an attack against our social and moral order.49 In that sense, sex offences such as bigamy, incest or homo-

4 8 Devlin, op. cit., pp. 7-8. 49 “Take, for example, the institution of marriage. Whether a man should be allowed to take more than one wife is something about which every society has to make up its mind one way or the other. In England we believe in the Christian idea of marriage and therefore adopt monogamy as a moral principle. Consequently the Christian institution of marriage has become the basis of family life and so part of the structure of our society. It is there not because it is Christian. It has got there because it is Christian, but it remains there because it is built into the house in which we live and could not be removed without bringing it down.” Devlin, op. cit., p. 9. Note in Devlin’s words the idea that it is the man who takes a wife, and not the reverse, though man and woman are supposedly equal in our society. But this also is part of the social order and morality, and it takes more than philosophical ideas to make a shift in the common belief.

sexuality, which amount to the rejection of the accepted notion of marriage, are considered as crimes against the moral order, just as treason is regarded as a crime against the political order. The internal structures of society have to be protected; if they are per- mitted to be undermined, then society might collapse. The idea of “collapse” must, however, be understood in a philosophical sense. Lord Devlin means that a society will cease to exist, but only to become another society, based on different ideas; it is essential, owing to human nature, that the notion of society include the sharing of ideas – political, moral and ethical. Substantial changes in the ar- rangement of shared ideas may result in the total transformation of such society.60

One may be bothered by Lord Devlin’s “natural law” approach to social morality, or by his somehow obscure approval of authori- tarianism 51 illustrated by references to traditional (i.e. religious) morality, or his approval of the decision in the Shaw case. 2 On the other hand, closer analysis of his views allows the reader to dis- tinguish between the writer’s own feelings about which morality should prevail in the (English) law today, and how the process of acknowledging morality and enforcing morals should be defined.3 As a result of its internal structures, society has thus a right to judge morals and protect its own existence. Morals are not a matter of private judgment; all morality is public. The next ques- tion is whether a given act of (public) immorality, done in private or not, may cause harm to the moral or political structure of so- ciety? Before he looks for an answer to his third question, Lord Devlin is careful to see if there is a weapon available to punish such acts in the first place. Indeed, what is the use of condemning a person or banning a deed if the order cannot be enforced? He thinks that the state not only has the proper weapons to protect society, but also that it has all the weapons it may need, for there is no theoretical limit on the power of the state to legislate against immorality; its legislation would always fall under the good govern- ment theory. Vice and treason are treated analogically, as actions directed against social order. Therefore, since there is no private

50 See infra, and Devlin, op. cit., pp. 13-14; on the right of society to protect itself, see also: Dworkin, loc. cit., (1965-1966), 75 Yale L. J. 986, at pp. 989 ff.

51 Ison, loc. cit., (1967), 3 U. B. C. L. Rev. 263, at p. 272. 52 See Devlin, op. cit., pp. 13-14; 18, 86 ff., 100; Devlin claims that Mill would certainly have protested on Hart’s comments on paternalism and the enforcement of morality; Devlin, loc. cit., (1962-65), 1 Manit. L. S. J. 243, at p. 247.

58 Devlin, op. cit., pp. 13, n. 1, 115-117.

morality, a man’s sin cannot only affect himself; there are some areas where society as a whole is less affected, such as drunken- ness, but there are others where man’s sin directly affects the moral structure, such as sexual offences. All areas of morality may, there- fore, be the object of a special intervention of the state in order to ensure the protection of society.

Which specific areas will actually be regulated by the state? The answer to the third question rests upon a matter of policy. Each society, owing to its own concept of public order (of., the notion of shared ideas) will determine the areas in which it will allow the state to intervene at all times, and those where intervention will depend on particular circumstances. Lord Devlin proposes, as a rule of thumb, that the general rule should favor the toleration of a maximum freedom of every individual. Although there would be shifts in the limits of acceptable tolerance, the general rule would be sufficient to cover most cases. The real test would be that of “private behaviour”, as against that of so-called “private morality”. 54 If the private behaviour of the individual is considered harmful to society, then he should be punished as a criminal offender. The actual criterion by which the harmfulness would be gauged is that of the reasonable man, the man in the jury box or on the Olapham omnibus. This is not the “rational man”, who is able to study the rules of morality and rationalize the existence of society, nor the intellectual or the expert, philosopher or lawyer, but the reasonable person, whose reasoning will be a reflection of the general princi- ples of right minded persons on morality and immorality. 5

Not too much logic should be looked for in the legal process; individuals, and indeed society, have a natural abhorrence of com- mercialized vice and homosexuality. Since the existence of society depends on what ideas its members are prepared to share and toler- ate, the ultimate judgment should normally be that of the average member, or the average group of members, of society. Notwith- standing the difficulties in ascertaining public opinion, the reason- able man’s personal opinion seems more than sufficient for dealing in matters of moral order.

54 As proposed by the Wolfenden Committee, op. cit., para. 61. 55 See Lord Devlin’s comments on the role of the educated in a democratic society, op. cit., pp. 94-99; see John Stuart Mill, on the “tyranny of the majority”, John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, (London, 1859), cited in The Six Great Human- istic Essays of John Stuart Mill, Washington Square Press ed., p. 130; Rostow, E.V., The Enforcement of Morals, [1960] Camb. L. J. 174, at p. 185; contra: Dworldn, loc. cit., (1965-66), 75 Yale L. J. 986, at pp. 1000-1001, on feelings and morality.

Criminal law should be used to set the minimum standards of conduct of the individuals, whereas moral laws will set the maximum standards of conduct. In some instances, the law will serve as de- terrent, in others, as remedy; but the only acceptable criterion to be used in order to protect the moral structure of society is that of the “reasonable man”.

Now that the function of the state has been determined, one would like to know what the relationship between law and morality will be? Society being defined as a community of shared ideas, the courts become the guardian of the community. John Stuart Mill’s theories were not accepted in the nineteenth century” 6 because England did not have a morality problem that needed such solu- tions. The separation between law and morals was not welcomed, because society had integrated its religious and moral principles into its own structure. The concept of “harm to others” was, there- fore, superfluous, since society was protecting itself as a whole, not as a collection of individuals. This was also carried on in the Shaw case 5 when the moral welfare of the state was submitted as being the ultimate value of moral order.

Lord Devlin proposes a set of rules for the understanding of the relationship between law and morality. In the first place, there is a need for a sense of “right” and “wrong” in every society. In- deed, no human relationship could subsist permanently without this basic morality, or the ability to distinguish between right and wrong. While on the other hand, the basic morality is a subjective one, the general sense of right and wrong is universal; however, it may be said that there are no “true” beliefs, but rather a number of “common” beliefs, which form the core of common morality. Secondly, there are, in fact, bad laws, bad morals and bad societies, but it is not because a law or a society is a bad one that it is a non-law or a non-society. Besides, the idea of “bad” is a relative or a comparative one; a law might be a bad one because instead of serving society, it destroys it. It is, therefore, bad, although it is a valid law, and although many individuals may actually derive personal profit from its immediate application. 5s Finally, although

56 See infra, on Hart. 57 [19611 2 All E.R. 446. 58,,No one now is shocked by the idea that the lawyer is concerned simply with the law as it is and not as he thinks it ought to be. No one need be shocked by the idea that the law-maker is concerned with morality as it is. There are, have been, and will be bad laws, bad morals, and bad societies. Probably no law-maker believes that the morality he is enacting is false, but that does not make it true. Unfortunately bad societies can live on bad morals just as well as good societies on good ones.” Devlin, op. cit., p. 94.

one may theoretically conceive of morality and law as seperate ideas, it is in practice impossible to isolate them. Reason cannot find truth by its own operation; the law will inevitably be what the judge or the jury think it is, or ought to be. The idea of toleration is, there- fore, brought forward again in order to help both moralists and jurists; morality is a question of facts. Whether the judge, the jury or society as a whole (e.g. through the electoral voice) are prepared to tolerate a situation is a matter of fact. If they are to tolerate, then the weapons of the law will not reach the individuals; if they do not tolerate, then society’s punishment will restore the moral order.

The matter of punishment is one of the most difficult to ap- preciate in the area of enforcement of morals, with respect to both the nature and the quantum of punishment. Devlin does not adopt Stephen’s retributive theory of punishment, but he does not explain fully his opinion on the right of society to inflict pain or suffering on offenders, except as an expression of public disapproval. On the other hand, if one is to follow the author’s general theory, once it is accepted that society has a right to protect its own moral and political structures, the right to punish finds an explanation. Forms and quanta of punishment will therefore be a matter of common morality and public order, coupled with the “toleration of the maximum individual freedom that is consistent with the integrity of society”. 59

As opposed to Lord Devlin, who refers to the general sense of right and wrong in society, Professor Hart seeks to rationalize the human activity: the problem is “one of critical morality about the legal enforcement of positive morality”. 60 Speaking of the in- terinfluence of law and morals, he discusses the existence or inte- gration of morality in the definition of a legal system, and introduces the concept of critical morality. Throughout this analysis, however, Hart pursues one goal – the contemporary demonstration of the validity of John Stuart Mill’s position on the legal enforcement of morality – although he expressly states that he does not approve of all of Mill’s theories 61 and even acknowledges that Stephen’s 62

59 Devlin, op. cit., pp. 16 ff.; Hart, op. cit., pp. 34 ff., 59-60

(see infra); Ginsberg, M., Book Review, [1964] Brit. J. of Criminology 283, at pp. 287-288; see infra, nn. 75, 107.

6 Hart, op. cit., p. 20. 61 “I shall consider this dispute mainly in relation to the special topic of sexual morality where it seems prima facie plausible that there are actions immoral by accepted standards and yet not harmful to others. But to prevent misunderstanding I wish to enter a caveat: I do not propose to defend all that

and Devlin’s theories may be more popular than Mill’s. 3 In short, Mill’s stand was that immorality as such is not a crime; “the only purpose for which power can rightfully be exercised over any member of a civilized community against his will is to prevent harm to others”. 64 In his own way, Professor Hart endeavours to justify this principle and rebuke Lord Devlin’s (and others’) 65 theory that morality should be envisaged in a positive way, 6 that is, to

Mill said; for I myself think that there may be grounds justifying the legal coercion of the individual other than the prevention of harm to others. But on the narrower issue relevant to the enforcement of morality Mill seems to be right.” Hart, op. cit., p. 5.

62 Stephen, J. F., Liberty, Equality, Fraternity, 2nd ed., (London, 1874). 63 Hart, op. cit., p. 17. 64 Mill, op. cit., p. 135; Mill continues as follows: “His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier, because, in the opinion of others, to do so would be wise, or even right. These are good reasons for remonstrating with him, or reasoning with him, or persuading him or entreating him, but not for compelling him, or visiting him with any evil, in case he do otherwise. To justify that, the conduct from which it is desired to deter him must be calculated to produce evil to someone else. The only part of the conduct of anyone, for which he is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign.”

65We shall not endeavour to review all opinions here; Hart has discussed the view of J. F. Stephen, who in his time opposed Mill’s theory; see Hart, op. cit., pp. 34 ff., 49, 55 ff.; Stephen, J. F., op. cit., supra, n. 62 and especially the preface to the second edition.

66 Here is how Devlin sees Mill’s approach to the legal enforcement of morals: “While the political scientists and constitution-makers of the age were engaged in separating Church and State, the philosophers came near to separating law and morality. Austin taught that the only force behind the law was physical force. Mill declared that the only purpose for which that force could rightfully be used against any member of the community was to prevent harm to others; his own good, physical or moral, was not sufficient warrant.

But this sort of thinking made no impact at all upon the development or administration of the English criminal law. This was doubtless because no practical problems arose. If there had been a deep division in the country on matters of morals – if there had been, for example, a large minority who wished to practice polygamy – the theoretical basis for legislation on morals would have had to have been scrutinized. But the Englishman’s hundred religions about which Voltaire made his jibe gave rise to no differences on morals grave enough to affect the criminal law. Parliament added incest and homosexual offences to the list of crimes without inquiring what harm they did to the community if they were committed in private; it was enough that they were morally wrong.” Devlin, op. cit., pp. 86-87;

“Now Professor Hart drafts his modifications so that he retains the two principles (as interpreted by himself) and two out of the eight specific crimes,

ensure the protection of society in its moral structure. “Harm to others” should be the test for the legal enforcement of morals, although the enforcement of morality as such may be admitted in some instances such as the punishment of cruelty against animals. Hart summarizes Devlin’s thoughts in two formulas: (a) that the law’s function is to “enforce a moral principle and nothing else”; 67 (b) “that he appears to move from the acceptable proposition that some shared morality is essential to the existence of any society to the unacceptable proposition that a society is identical with its morality as that is at any given moment of its history, so that a change in its morality is tantamount to the destruction of a society… the latter proposition is absurd. 68 … There is no evidence that the preservation of a society requires the enforcement of its morality ‘as such’. His position only appears to escape this criticism by a confused definition of what a society is.” 69 Such statements on the part of the two writers have only led to disagreement. It would appear, at first sight, that Professor Hart has not fully appreciated the fact that Lord Devlin is not concerned about the enforcement of morality as such, but that he is worrying about the protection of society as a “going concern”.70

namely bigamy and cruelty to animals. One of the crimes, homosexuality, he would abolish.” Devlin, loc. cit., (1962-1965), 1 Manit. L. S. J. 243, at p. 245. As indicated by Lord Devlin, Mill was, at the time of his writings, attracted more by the economic matters, and the prevailing laissez faire atmosphere than by morals as such. Nowadays, morality seems to be a major preoccupation. See ibid., at pp. 248-249, on Mill’s religion and common morality. Devlin concludes his remarks on Mill as follows: “.. Mill’s doctrine is just as dogmatic as any of those he repudiates. It is dogmatic to say that if only we were allowed to behave just as we liked so long as we did not injure each other the world would become a better place for all of us. There is more evidence for this sort of utopia than there is evidence of the existence of heaven…”, ibid., at p. 253. The other crimes referred to by Mill are abortion, buggery and bestiality, incest, obscenity (pornography) and offences relating to prostitution and the commer- cialization of vice. “Professor Hart is silent about all of them, although there are indications that he would grant neither to abortion nor to the commercializa- tion of vice the full protection afforded by the private realm.” Ibid., at p. 245.

67 Hart, op. cit., p. 32. 6sidem. p. 51. 69 Idem, p. 82. 70Lord Devlin stated: “I do not assert that any deviation from a society’s shared morality threatens its existence any more than I assert that any sub- versive activity threatens its existence. I assert that they are both activities which are capable in their nature of threatening the existence of society so that neither can be put beyond the law.

For the rest, the objection appears to me all a matter of words. I would venture to assert, for example, that you cannot have a game without rules and

Whereas Lord Devlin held that the legal enforcement of morality was necessary to protect the moral structure of society, and that the test of morality was the reasonable man’s opinion, Professor Hart suggests that ‘harm to others” is the only purpose for which the law may be imposed on individual liberty. Strictly speaking, we need not go further in order to confront Hart with the underlying principles of his own theory; indeed, “harm to others” is meaningful only when one has been able to determine what sort of “harm” will hurt which “others.” In other terms, “harm to others” presupposes a complete set of value judgments that will be found in each society’s own structure and inner morality; the concepts of “harm” and “others” can only by appreciated through a set of relative values, which in turn must depend on a given notion of society as a whole and as composed of individuals. Therefore, even though this approach will not favorably approve of the enforcement of morality as such, it will nevertheless approve of the use of the law to compensate for harm done to others, on the assumption that this particular society or group, through its common morality, sees harm and evil in the consequences of a given deed. Instead of envisaging the broad consequences of the deed with respect to the moral structure of society, this type of valuation is limited to the more immediate effects upon the individuals, as victims of the immoral deed. But notwithstanding the number and depth of areas examined, the appreciation necessarily requires a system of values which cannot be but based on a given society’s concept of morality and legal sanctions. One of the most obvious examples of the absence of “harm to others” (on purpose, homosexuality will not be included here) is that of suicide and of attempted suicide. Should only the interest and well being of the individuals be concerned in the definition of morality and of the legal enforcement of morals, unsuccessful at- tempts to commit suicide would not fall under the rule of morality since there would be no harm to others. Only in a broader concept

that if there were no rules there would be no game. If I am asked whether that means that the game is ‘identical’ with the rules, I would be willing for the question to be answered either way in the belief that the answer would lead to nowhere. If I am asked whether a change in the rules means that one game has disappeared and another has taken its place, I would reply probably not, but that it would depend on the extent of the change.” Devlin, op. cit., p. 13, n. 1. See Hart’s reply to this reply: (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1, at p. 9, n. 21; see infra, n. 79. “I think that the attempt by the (Wolfenden) Committee does break down and that this is shown by the fact that it has to define or describe its special circumstances so widely that they can be supported only if it is accepted that the law is concerned with immorality as such.” Devlin, op. cit., p. 11; see Hart, op. cit., p. 52.

of society and morality will such deeds be punished, therefore affect- ing Hart’s theory on two grounds: by an implication that the indi- vidual alone cannot form a proper and complete basis for the appreciation of morality, and by the necessity of having a particular and supple set of values by which morality and immorality can be defined and enforced.71

Many difficulties are encountered in this process, however; it has been said that such crimes as attempted suicide and abortion are the object and result of attempts to enforce morality “as such”,7 2 or that the mere multiplication of so many examples of a species do not allow the observer to draw a strict rule as to the existence of a legal or moral rule. But, on the other hand, an unenforced or an unenforceable law is nevertheless a law, and the actual enforce- ment of some rules relating to morals (even mere fornification or adultery) 73 is a form of enforcement of morality. Which morality, though? It seems doubtful that the simple “harm to others” test can be applied here. Another objection is the “paternalism” argu- ment,74 where, for instance, criminal law never admits the consent of the victim as a defence on behalf of the accused. Hart suggests that far from being an instrument for enforcing moral principles, the rules of the criminal law in such cases are only pieces of paternalism, designed to protect individuals against themselves. Whether this interpretation is good or bad, however, it does not help the “harm to others” theory. Since it is unlikely that society will change such rules of criminal law, it means that the “harm to others” theory will have to be expanded to include harm to oneself; this situation also shows the necessity of having a system of moral values to define the idea of harm and, in this instance, elucidate the would be paternalistic attitude of society. It would, therefore, appear that harming others becomes the basis of “positive morality” not in the narrow interpretation of the idea of harm, but in the widest possible sense that society as a whole, and as composed

71 Newsweek magazine ran a cover story on morality on November 13, 1967, “Anything goes: Taboos in Twilight”, and quoted a counsel of the U.S. Post Office as saying: “Sex is troubling for society, but government ought to stay out of it, unless there is widespread licentiousness which becomes harmful. The Government is not here to enforce the Ten Commandments, and the wants of society are generally twenty years ahead of government?’ (p. 77).

72 Hart, op. cit., pp. 25-26. 7 3 Idem, p. 27, citing Massachusetts statistics; many other states have such laws which are enforced from time to time, as a result of either public or private action. The Playboy Foundation has pledged its resources and services for helping those who are the victims of such laws.

74 See supra, n. 52.

of individuals, is concerned both about its own structure and about the well being of its members. The notion of harm would definitely be linked to a system of moral and social values.

This becomes particularly evident in the area of punishment. Punishment, and the threat of punishment, are intended to prevent further occurrences of evil and suffering or harm. Criminal law, for example, is not principally directed to the prevention of evil; it may prevent evil by fear of punishment, but otherwise it is only a sanction. It is not only the suffering that must be considered here, nor the immorality of causing pain or suffering, but the whole process of cause and consequence, since one could not exist without the other. When society has to consider the quantum of punishment, it does so on the relative moral wickedness of the act done; it, therefore, follows that the theory of punishment is also based on a theory of values, that is to say, on a given concept of positive morality, supplemented by legal weapons to ensure its enforcement. The effectiveness of punishment results from the combination of the evil of suffering with the evil of immorality in order to produce a moral good. Once it is admitted that punishment should be related to the relative moral wickedness of the offender and of the act committed, the whole theory of “harm to others” collapses, or rather is absorbed by the broader concept of morality as a social value, based upon a society’s positive morality. Hart states the following:

(T)hey can in perfect consistency insist on the one hand that the only justification for having a system of punishment is to prevent harm and only harmful conduct should be punished, and, on the other, agree that when the question of the quantum of punishment for such conduct is raised, we should defer to principles which make relative moral wickedness of different offenders a partial determinant of the severity of punishment.75 This dual approach to morality is not convincing: it distinguishes theoretical values (e.g. the system of punishment) from practical ones (e.g. the quantum of punishment). If the intention or the means of the offender does not make the harm caused more harmful, then unequal punishments can only find some justification in the morality of the immoral, that is, in social values and the desire of enforcing positive morality. Hart’s own terms would seem to allow such an interpretation, and thus weaken the “harm to others” theory:

(I)n the theory of punishment, what is in the end morally tolerable is apt to be more complex than our theories initially suggest. We cannot usually in social life pursue a single value or a single moral aim, untroubled by the need to compromise with others.76

75 Hart, op. cit., p. 37, and (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1, at p. 7; Hart cites

Durkeim’s Division of Labor in Society; see nn. 59 and 107.

7 6 Hart, op. cit., p. 38.

Professor Hart criticizes Lord Devlin’s theory as being a seamless web; this is not much more than labelism; however, it is true that all social moralities possess universal values 7 that are deemed essential to society and common morality and “worth preserving even at the cost in terms of those same values which legal enforce- ment involves”.78 Devlin’s idea of society as a community of shared ideas leaves much leeway for adaptation to social evolution, at least so far as the “reasonable man” (the jury) is made the arbiter of social evolution within the juridicial sphere. Moreover, perhaps the seamless web concept would have helped Hart in the application of the “harm to others” theory, which is not as simple in real life as in the sayings of the writer.79 At the outcome, however, Hart and Devlin do not stand very far apart, since both Hart’s “harm to others” principle and Devlin’s protection of society’s moral structure rest on a very similar necessity, that is, a system of values particular to each society concerned. This debate on the legal enforcement of morality relates itself to the problem of the relationship between law

77 Such as individual freedom, safety of life and protection from deliberately

inflicted harm. See Hart, op. cit., p. 70.

78 Hart, op. cit., p. 70. 79 See Devlin, op. cit., p. 13, n. 1, supra, note 70. “So, with permissiveness in the area formally covered by restrictive morality, there would come increase in violence and dishonesty and a general lapse of those restraints which are essen- tial for any form of social life. This is the view that the morality of the individual constitutes a seamless web.” Hart, loc. cit., (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1, at p. 13; see also pp. 9, n. 21, and 12-13; see Devlin, op. cit., p. 115;

However, any permissiveness or relaxation would take place in due course, as society is able to bear the change, so that no real upset in social order would result. If the evolution is rapid or revolutionary, society will react in another way, trying to protect its security through a new social order. But to call the human feelings a seamless web, or a vicious circle, means nothing if it is not an acknowledgement of one’s incapability of discerning the fundamental motives and pattern of human behaviour. See Hart, (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1, at p. 13; Hart is right in saying that he sees no evidence of desintegration, for society rarely disintegrates, notwithstanding Devlin’s use of that word. Evolution and transformation might have been more appropriate, as societies are under a constant process of evolution, as a result of the continuous movement of persons and ideas. Psychologists, sociologists and other scientific experts have yet to explain the common morality, and one may doubt whether the pattern of human and social behaviour will ever be explained and rationalized. We may be moving from religious morality to ‘moral pluralism’ or to permissiveness, but those very expressions already take us from the basic ideas of common morality and public order to the more subjective realm of value judgements and political or social systems. Any thesis chosen to explain the common morality will not do more than explain what its author sees through his own deficiencies, and names will not change the substance. One should be prepared to admit beforehand that his suggestion is only one of the possible theories.

and morality, a perennial source of controversies among legal phi- losophers; there is, however, in Professor Hart’s own words an admission which could reconcile him with his opponents:

… liability for both civil and criminal The influence of morality on law. – wrongs may be adjusted to prevailing views of moral responsibility. No ‘positivist’ could deny that these are facts, or that the stability of legal systems depends in part upon such types of correspondence with morals. If this is what is meant by the necessary connexion of law and morals, its existence should be conceded.80

Common Morality and the Toleration of Immorality; Problems of guidance to the legislature and the judiciary

The Hart-Devlin debate has not been granted the same con- sideration and interest by critics and legal philosophers; Devlin himself refused to be carried further into what he called a battle of words.8 1 On the other hand, he did not refrain from restating his basic policy. Other critics have found themselves Devlinians or Hartians, and sometimes both at the same time on different aspects of the legal enforcement of morals.

On the subject matter of homosexuality, Professor Fuller found the “argument quite inconclusive on both sides, resting as it does on initial assumptions that are not made explicit in the argument itself”.8 2 To him, this question is a far simpler one, and here he raises Lord Devlin’s second question: there ought to be no law making it a crime for consenting adults to engage privately in homo- sexual acts, because such a law cannot be enforced. It would consti- tute an open invitation to blackmail, so that there would be a gaping discrepancy between the law as written and its enforcement in practice. This has, unfortunately, been the case, except in such far fetched instances as the Klippert case 83 where a single person has to pay for all the unattended cases. Fuller’s conclusion is of the simplest kind: “I suggest that many related issues can be resolved

80 Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law, (Oxford, 1961), pp. 199-200; also p. 207; “If, however, Professor Hart means that it ‘would be wrong’ for law-makers to act on the basis of disgust alone; that they should make a separate and inde- pendent judgment that a practice is injurious to society as well as odious; that they should consider the implications of the half dozen qualifying principles whose exposition requires almost one third of Sir Patrick’s lecture, then I fail to understand how his (Hart’s) position differs from that of the Justice (Devlin).” Rostow, loc. cit., [1960] Camb. L.J. 174, at p. 189.

81 Devlin, op. cit., p. 13, n. 1. 82 Fuller, L. L., The Morality of Law, (New Haven and London, 1965), pp.

83 See discussion, supra, at pp. 11 ff.

in similar terms without having to reach agreement on the sub- stantive moral issues involved.” 84

To that the present writer would agree if the actual situations calling for the legal enforcement of morals were quite simple, and if society and its pressure groups could easily be convinced that the law will be unenforceable, or that some other technical difficulty rules out the necessity of finding agreement on, or of arriving at, a definition of certain substantive moral issues. However, such issues often arise at such times and under such circumstances when society faces an internal crisis, or when an unexpected event calls for urgent remedies where legislators or judges do not benefit from the calm and cool reasoning of legal philosophers. Every generation brings its own censors who claim that moral decay is ruining the foundation of society; what happens, though, is that society itself is under a constant evolution, through a purely natural and spon- taneous process, and with it the concepts of public and moral order. True, in a society that is totalitarian, as where, for example, religion has been made one of the corner-stones of the political regime, the legal enforcement of morals appears as a necessity and an essential condition of this society’s survival. Further examples may be found in some communist regimes, where one of the primary functions of the law is to enforce morality, that is, morality adopted for the time being by the “party”; regulations affecting hygiene and sexual morality in state residences and housing, or waste of public property are considered as essential to maintain the common morality. On the other hand, in a “democratic” state where religion as such is not the basis of the political order, but has been used as a model for, say, defining the goals of a Christian political society, public order will not be affected very seriously by the toleration of immoral acts. 85 The legal enforcement of morals raises the conflicts between individual ethics and social morality. The evolution of morality has not been, if at all, the sole factor of moral or social decay, whatever these concepts mean. It is too easy to reject changes in the name of “social decay” without due consideration for the underlying nature of each society.”” Whether one adopts Devlin’s approach and stands by the reasonable man’s opinion or feelings as to when should the law be used to enforce morality, or Hart’s rational view that law and morality should not be mistaken, with the exception that harm caused by immoral deeds will justify the use of legal weapons, the

s4 Fuller, op. cit., p. 133. 85 Devlin, op. cit., p. 9. 86 On society, see Hart, loc. cit., (1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1, and the refer-

ences cited.

ultimate outcome will depend not on the method used but on the system under examination. Since societies are constantly changing, so will the relationship between law and morality and the basis for the legal enforcement of morals. To a considerable extent, all laws are connected with the legal enforcement of morals: regulations concerning education, taxation, social welfare, old age, housing and municipal administration are necessary to ensure the proper conduct of society. The allocation of cost and other responsibilities reflect the common morality and need the action of the law to be properly executed8 7 Any society possesses such a common morality and has the power to enforce it according to its own legal system; but the legal enforcement of the common morality still leaves way for the individual’s responsibility to make the necessary social and moral judgments. Society will only seek the enforcement of the rules when public order, as defined in each case, is endangered.

Legal philosophers have worried about the need for sufficient guidance to legislators in dealing with matters of morality, and especially when the public opinion is divided. Devlin has been criticized for leaving the matter to the judgment of the reasonable man, whereas Hart’s “harm to others” criterion leaves the matter open to a further case of interpretation – what is harm, what is the relation between immoral deeds and the harm caused, and how to determine the quantum of punishment? Experience has shown, however, that guidance is not always an easy answer to this problem; depending on the type of society that has to be dealt with in the first place, one must also consider the system of values attached to the legislative and judiciary process, and then appreciate the immediate circumstances in which morality or immorality has to be valued. Democracy, free press and urbanization are factors which influence the legal enforcement of morals. Knowing that a case of homosexuality is to be tried in a small town with a highly religious or conservative jury, one might not be prepared to recommend that the man in the jury box be the final judge. On the other hand, one might well be!

One should remember that “society” is as vague a concept as “morality”, “justice” or “equality”, which are convenient abstractions to work with, but are quite difficult to define in practice; since both law and morality vary with the nature and structure of each society, absolute or definitive rules in this field can only belong to Utopia. Bias and prejudice are as much a part of our social values as religion or social order. For centuries, our societies have been

8 7 Rostow, loc. cit., [1960] Camb. L.J. 174, at pp. 196-197.

organized on the assumption that males are superior to females, and white people superior to colored people; this has resulted in a peculiar morality that affects individuals, spouses, families, social, economic and political activities and countless particular rules of behaviour, including the criminal law. Religious belief and natural law have also been prime factors in the determination of common morality.

But although most cases of immorality have some connexion with sexual matters, not all immorality is sexual; in the medieval ages, heresy used to be a classical example of immorality calling for the use of legal weapons. Although such crimes as heresy and blasphemy no longer exist in our society (at least for the time being), Lord Devlin’s parallel between morals and treason is fully warranted. Granted that society has both a political and moral structure, though there might be other ways of classifying those aspects of social activity, attacks against the very nature of society may call for legal punishment. The notion of harm to others would be very difficult to appreciate, for example, in the case of Luther or Marx or other writers whose works have had deep and long lasting effects on social and moral structures. Legal philosophy, to some extent, must deal with problems ex tempore. The idea of harm must not necessarily be taken as bodily harm, and the changing of social structures as an instantaneous phenomenon. Homosexuality, for example, may or may not result in what is called social and moral decay; moreover, with the difficulties encountered in the prose- cution of presumed guilty palties, the actual punishment of a convicted homosexual is more of an exemplary sanction than of an equitable punishment. But how is the damage or harm to society being valuated? Time is a fairly small factor in this process. The more critical one gets about the so-called criteria of morality, the more one realizes how dependent the law is on social values and common morality. After all, one may now very well question whether Galileo or Luther were the authors of immoral deeds. Morality, on the whole, would then be what each society, in its own time is prepared to accept as moral, and unless one is prepared to accept the existence of natural law, being outside the reach of human beings as individuals or as groups, then one must accept that morality, and, as a direct and necessary consequence, the legal en- forcement of morality, is not susceptible of a fixed definition or valuation. Since each society determines its own legal system, the relationship between law and morals is thus the object of a constant renewal, notwithstanding some elements of continuity. But even if one went as far as to accept natural law as an imperative set of

rules, implied or not, social morality would, nevertheless, remain as a determinant factor in the legal enforcement of morals.88

Problems of guidance to legislature and judiciary are not theo- retical ones; that was the purpose of the Wolfenden Report. Just as the United Kingdom has given itself a new Act on homosexuality 89 and abortion, 90 the Parliament of Canada is studying a new bill dealing with those matters, and Governor Rockefeller, for the second consecutive year, is trying to have the legislature of the State of New York adopt a new law on abortion.9 1 The death penalty has been the subject of lengthy debates both in Canada and the United Kingdom, 92 and such topics as divorce, drug addiction and many others are the constant subject of open debates at all levels of society and law making agencies. It may be necessary to remember, however, the exaggerated attention that has been devoted to sexual matters, in connexion with the enforcement of morals. Tax swindlers or traffic offenders, the most usual types of “upper class” wrongdoers, are as much guilty of immoral deeds in our society as sexual offenders. On the other hand, there have been cases of non sexual immorality that have raised wide interest and concern: members of the legis- lature or public servants accepting bribes or dissipating or using public or political funds for their private use, persons who could have rescued a child who was about to be drowned or hit by a vehicle, but who abstained from doing what they could, and the moral responsibility of cigarette manufacturers and their publicity agents. The recent introduction of the breathalizer test in the United Kingdom for preventing and punishing dangerous driving as a result

88 See supra, n. 70, ref. Devlin; Hart, op. cit., pp. 51-52, 82; Ginsberg, loc. cit., [1964] Brit. J. Criminology 283, at p. 289; Henkin, L., Morals and the Constitu- tion: the Sin of Obscenity, (1963), 63 Col. L. Rev. 391; Schwartz, L. B.; Moral Offences and the Model Penal Code, (1963), 63 Col. L. Rev. 669.

89 Sexual Offences Act, 1967, c. 60. 90 Abortion Act, 1967, c. 87. 91 California has a new abortion law since November 8, 1967; see a review

of the problem in the New York Times, January 8, 1968.

92 The law was voted in the House of Commons (Canada) on Nevember 23, 1967, abolishing capital punishment for murder, except in the slaying of police- men and prison guards. The validity of the law extends to a period of five years only. Death penalty remains in force for rape and treason. The prime minister of Canada stated that capital punishment is not effective enough as a deterrent for murder to justify its retention. The real causes of crime were slums, ghettos and personality disorders. A former minister of justice, now in the opposition, said that the preservation of society required that anyone who deliberately takes a life has forfeited the right to live. – Party lines were raised for the voting. New York Times, November 24, 1967, pp. 1, 22; House of Commons Debates, November 23, 1967, V, pp. 4604-4606.

of drinking alcohol is yet another example; Sweden has had similar dispositions for many years. Those are increasingly becoming matters of public concern, thus forcing society to investigate its common morality and the legal enforcement of morals.9 3

Modern society disposes of new instruments to take its own pulse; at one time, the man on the Clapham omnibus could be allowed to value the relative morality of a situation. Increased sophistication may not take from him this essential role, but society will now provide him with scientific apparatus and knowledge so that he can perform his tasks. Sociological, psychological or economic enquiries, research, the increasing use of medical or other experts, fact finding agencies, trends and tendencies analysts will enable the man in the jury box, whose personal knowledge is by definition insignificant, and whose once reliable common sense is vanishing, to evaluate the moral pulse of society. It may well be that Bentham’s censorial jurisprudence, Hart’s critical morality or Devlin’s equity and reason have all been absorbed by a society that is changing at an increasingly rapid pace and that has to adjust its own rules to its new existence. If, however, we are struck by the “medieval rhetoric” of Viscount Simonds in the Shaw case 94 or the “I would rather stick to the law” attitude of Fauteux, J., in the Canadian Klippert case, 95 we must take into consideration some other factors, such as the personality of those two men, the traditionally assumed rule that in England and Canada the courts will not act as law making agencies when Parliament could properly do so, and the prevailing social atmos- phere of the time. The Shaw case followed a recent amendment of the Sexual Offences Act, and it may have been feared, as is evidenced by the prosecution’s brief, that an over-liberal test case might result in abuses.9 6 The Canadian case, on the other hand, was dealt with by the Supreme Court of Canada just after the homosexual amend- ment in the United Kingdom, and just as the Minister of Justice had announced oncoming legislative reforms in this area. This may help to explain the decision.

But if the reasonable man’s view of morality can be acceptable on the judicial level, who is going to fulfil his task in the legisla- ture? This question would seem even easier to answer, because

93 See Newsweek, November 13, 1967, supra, n. 71. 04 [1961] 2 All E. R. 446 (H. L.). 05 [19671 S.C.R. 822. 96 On the other hand, the logic of the House of Lord’s majority reasoning and of its traditional conception might have led it to take a more modest view of its own role, on account of the recent activities of the legislator. See the debate in the Columbia Law School Centennial (1953).

judicial cases have to be dealt with as they arise, whereas legislative bills are usually introduced when the government is good and ready to do so. In such regimes as totalitarian politics, the party’s ideology or the internal bureaucratic structure normally provide answers to moral problems. Immoral deeds exist in greater number because those societies have a greater need to protect themselves, and legal enforcement is hardly a problem as a result of a variety of efficient weapons and remedies.

Democratic societies, on the other hand, often have to depend on individual action for raising moral issues. Morality and the legal enforcement of morals often have to be attacked by way of resist- ance or civil disobedience before being the object of adapted legisla- tion. In some instances, a government or political party will pledge itself to the enactment of reforms affecting common morality and public order, or, such reforms will be proposed in the form of a private member’s bill. When reforms are long overdue, and there is evidence that the legal rule is now beyond the common morality, governments and parliaments will simply act upon the bill as a matter of routine. If the issue is not all clear, a private member’s bill is more likely, since no government will assume such responsi- bility, for fear of being told by the electorate that it had moved ahead of the common morality. Less doubtful subject matters are likely to provoke endless debates or filibuster in Parliament, and when the time comes for voting, party lines will be raised so that each member will be allowed to act as a man in the jury box, using both his common and political sense to vote upon the measure; the common morality is well served by such a procedure, and so is the government, whose party does not bear the responsibility for the vote. American legislatures do not follow this pattern, but generally attain similar results; bills are introduced by the government but have to go through a complex pattern of committee and legislative sessions where the common wisdom and morality is evaluated, and congressmen do not necessarily follow their party lines in voting on any bill, thus perpetuating the reasonable man’s common sense. 7

97 “The democratic system of government goes some way –

not all the way, for no representative can be the mirror of the voters’ thoughts – to ensure that the decision of the law-naker will be acceptable to the majority, but the majority is not the whole …

But under the second theory the law-maker is not required to make any judgment about what is good and what is bad. The morals which he enforces are those ideas about right and wrong which are already accepted by the society for which he is legislating and which are necessary to preserve its integrity. He has not to argue with himself about the merits of monogamy and polygamy; he has merely to observe that monogamy is an essential part of the structure

Politics would, therefore, appear as inseparable from morality. However, one has to query whether, in the process of social and moral evolution, there can be changes in morality. Natural lawyers, and many legal philosophers would think that moral standards do not shift: 98 they do not, so far as one is prepared to admit that they come from a superior divine source, or are simply built into human nature. Some aspects of morality, on the other hand, are more easily questioned, and would seem to rest on a purely con- sensual, or merely social, basis. Monogamy, for instance, although practiced by most societies nowadays, is not, and has not been, universal, as it has yielded to polygamy in areas where living con- ditions made it useful or necessary. Although most societies are more or less religious and have in some cases been greatly influenced by their religious practices, it is obvious that religious morals are not all alike, and that there tends to be an increasing division be- tween the common morality of a given society and the religious morals that have influenced its formation. Although adultery, forni- cation and usury ranked equally as both sins and immoral crimes in the medieval Christian society, the same are not always regarded as sins by most contemporary societies.99

Whether morality and moral standards shift, or should be re- garded as shifting, or not, is a matter which will very likely not be solved, as long as human beings have limited means of knowl- edge. In fact, this is more a matter of religious belief, and the churches themselves have had to revise their concepts of morality; Galileo’s case is perhaps the easiest to understand nowadays. What worries us in a democratic society is how to assess the shift in the social toleration of departures from moral standards. In the first place, although there is a general feeling that there is a shift in

of the society to which he belongs. Naturally he will assume that the morals of his society are good and true; if he does not, he should not be playing an active part in government. But he has not to vouch for their goodness and truth. His mandate is to preserve the essentials of his society, not to reconstruct them according to his own ideas.” Devlin, op. cit., pp. 89-90; see also Ison’s rather humoristic comment on how a bill on homosexual behaviour was voted in ‘Ruri- tania’; loc. cit., (1967), 3 U. B.C. L. Rev. 263, at pp. 270-271; Dworkin, loc. cit., (1965-66), 75 Yale L.J. 986, at pp. 994-999, and 1002.

08 Devlin, op. cit., pp. 18, 5-7. 99 Henkin, lco. cit., (1963), 63 Col. L. Rev. 391, at p. 407. “No doubt a critical morality based on the theory that all social morality had the status of divine commands or of eternal truth discovered by reason would not for obvious reasons now seem plausible. It is perhaps least plausible in relation to sexual morals, determined as these so obviously are by variable tastes and conventions.” Hart, op. cit., p. 73, and see pp. 7S-74.

tolerance, it is not all that easy to determine the swing and inten- sity of such shifts. It is true that moral standards, that is the individual’s attitude towards morality, change with each generation, but there is no sure method of evaluating this phenomenon, since modern communication media often tend to distort the available information.

Surely, there is a tolerance shift; contraception, abortion, drug addiction or homosexuality have all been at least accepted as topics for open discussion, whereas earlier moral standards banned them from “honest” circles. Yet, the traditional divisions remain be- tween (a) common morality, (b) social tolerance to some form of immorality and the changing of common morality, (c) the legal enforcement of morality, or the use of legal weapons to punish immorality. Devlin’s preliminary question concerning the right of society to judge morals and the existence of proper weapons to deal with immorality now seem to have found answers. Common morality is perhaps the most difficult to define, but also the least interesting as regards the matter of legal enforcement. The lawyer and the legal philosopher will want to know which immoral deeds society is not prepared to tolerate, and which among those it is prepared to punish expressly. It is almost impossible to assume any regular or phased evolution; social tolerance cannot be predicted, and it is not always easy to introduce or repeal a law dealing with morality or immo- rality; it often takes a number of years before the two are permitted to coincide, if ever.

Most critics of the Wolfenden Report agree in rejecting the Committee’s test of “private morality”; Devlin suggests that a test of “private behaviour” should be substituted, 100 and Hart sug- gests that the “harm to others” idea should be retained. But is this the proper approach to the enforcement of morals ? Of course, this query takes place in a democratic context where society does not require a special moral behaviour from its members, although some writers seem to take for granted that there is some inherent rule of private morality or behaviour that citizens should obey. This is much more evident in the ‘area of sexual morality, and tends to disappear almost entirely in other areas of morality, such as eco- nomic or social behaviour (e.g. tax dodging), where the common morality serves as the only criterion. In sexual matters, however, the individual is given a particular duty to contribute to the com- mon good by his own private behaviour, and it is this conduct that will or will not be tolerated by the community.

100 Devlin, op. cit., p. 19.

Apart from natural law or religious morality, so called private morality has no bearing on common morality in a democratic society. Indeed, all morality is social and serves social goals: there being no such thing as private morality. Common morality will find its manifestations through the members of the society, but whether a deed is good or bad for one individual or for the society is not a matter of private concern; it may be wrong in terms of religious morality, but not necessarily in terms of social morality. The be- haviour of individuals and the use of legal weapons to punish such behaviour as it is judged socially immoral have to be considered through society’s morality and agencies. For example, societies have, at other times, regarded homosexuality as socially immoral; modern societies are, however, faced with such a rule that has proven very difficult to universally and equitably enforce. Certain countries have now come to questioning whether homosexuality is after all a danger for the public order and should be treated as socially immoral.

This is but one example of the shift in social tolerance towards morality. There were some periods where homosexuality was re- garded as a normal manifestation of sexuality and even as a military advantage. 10’ Canada is now considering whether it should adjust its criminal law to the common morality and adopt legislation simi- lar to the recent United Kingdom Act. On the other hand, the Ameri- can society has shown little sign that homosexuality would cease to be regarded as a social evil, notwithstanding the action of pressure groups and the social discrimination that results from the prevailing social morality.10 2

There is, however, no strict rule that enables the legal philoso- pher to advise his government on how to handle common morality and the legal punishment of immorality. Laws are by no means perfect instruments to deal with morality, and generally are either too strict or too lenient; for example, laws prohibiting homosexuality have never been efficient. One is always surprised to see that al- though prostitution as such is not a criminal offence, the fact of being a common prostitute is, but habitual male partners of female common prostitutes are not prosecuted. The consent of a victim cannot be raised as a defence by the accused. Those examples show how imperfect the rules are, and yet, it is not very easy to make better ones, that is, rules that would be adapted to the common morality, and at the same time equitable and enforceable. The government has a right and a duty to protect society and its moral

101 See Bertrand Russell, Human Society in Ethics and Politics, p. 99, on the

Spartan’s theory that homosexuality promoted courage in battle.

102 See the New York Times, November 26, 1967.

values; in many instances it has been protecting groups and indi- viduals against themselves. But it is not usually efficient to tell a government that the laws it has enacted are ultra vires or that its rules do not fit the common morality. It is far easier to show it that its legislation, or its silence, is doing more harm than good, or at least is doing it more political harm than good, and to con- vince it that the rules for the enforcement of morals should be changed. 0 3

Social gain or common morality should be the real test for the regulation of morality and immorality. But here again, it is diffi- cult to assess in advance the limits of change and of tolerance. Society needs no law to make a father love his child, because it would in any case be unenforceable; but on the other hand, there are laws to force a father to support his children, although our society, through its common morality, fails in this respect by not forcing a father to support all his children, legitimate or not. Other areas are still more difficult to appreciate. Why should attempts to commit suicide be punished? Is it because it is an implied rejection of society as such or because of the harm to others, though indirect? How can such a crime be explained in terms of social goal, common morality and social tolerance ?104 Deeds, moral or immoral, will be punished by the law if the common morality and the limits of tolerance require that they be punished. 05 The pattern is definitely unpredictable, because social evolution takes place without uniform phasing, and always on the basis of a given society’s common mo- rality. One example will summarize this process. Birth control meth- ods were traditionally banned as a result of the adoption by our society of religious morality. Modern medicine has shown, however,

103 Devlin, op. cit., p. 117. 10 4 “No person is an entirely isolated being; it is impossible for a person to do anything seriously or permanently hurtful to himself, without mischief reaching at least to his near connections, and often far beyond them … If he deteriorates his bodily or mental faculties, he not only brings evil upon all who depended on him for any portion of their happiness, but disqualifies himself for rendering the services which he owes to his fellow-creatures generally; perhaps becomes a burden on their affection or benevolence; and if such conduct were very frequent, hardly any offence that is committed would detract more from the general sum of good. Finally, if by his vices or follies a person does no direct harm to others, he is nevertheless (it may be said) injurious by his example; and ought to be compelled to control himself, for the sake of those whom the sight or knowledge of his conduct might corrupt or mislead.” Mill, op. cit., pp. 204-205.

105 Devlin comments: whether a man, on being accused of bigamy, pleads that (a) he believed his wife was dead or (b) he believed bigamy is a good thing, society will reject his defence, on moral grounds: “We can’t be certain, we may be mistaken, but we must act upon our belief”. Such belief will determine the limits of tolerance. See (1962-65), 1 Manit. L. S. J. 243, at p. 252.

that such methods can be harmless, and indeed useful. Overpopulated countries may even reach a new social morality where it will become immoral not to control births, whereas the very capitalistic coun- tries who need substantial increases in population in order to keep up with their economic structures will perhaps make it socially immoral to over restrain births and endanger the community.

Should homosexuality, or abortion, or the use of contraception be legally punished? One can build up an answer according to philo- sophical or religious belief, but if one is to stand by sheer social reasoning, there is no answer to be given, or at least no answer that would be universally acceptable without due reference to social structures and common morality. Although one may recommend that the toleration of a maximum freedom be acknowledged to individuals, and that the law represent the minimum intervention in the affairs of the citizens, the real limits of tolerance, and the actual shifts in legal restrictions, will reflect what each society, through its own agencies, common morality and legal system, is prepared to tolerate or punish.” 6

To that extent, the Hart-Devlin debate has been helpful, but not as much as one would have expected. Any assumption of private or religious morality will only divert the analyst’s attention from social to individual problems of behaviour. Individual and social morality may result in a vicious circle if the basis for argumentation is too firm or narrow; otherwise, it may also become a matter of words and definitions where the same terms do not correspond to the same ideas. The problem here is not only philosophical; it also involves the actual enforcement of common morality and the underlying relationship between law and morality. Hart and Devlin have gone a long way towards the explanation of the legal enforcement of morals, but their debate is in fact a non-debate, for they hardly speak from the same standpoint. Strong principles will succeed in maintaining social order only if such principles have their roots in society as a “going concern” and not as an abstract idea. The implantation of strong moral rules in a society that advocates indi- vidual freedom and open democracy will not yield expected results. Any actions that are suspected of undermining society will have to be assessed and weighted by such society, owing to particular cir- cumstances. In the interpretation of the structure of society, Devlin chose a group-oriented solution, whereas Hart remained closer to

o6 Devlin, op. cit., pp. 14 and also 115: “But when considering the degree of injury to a public morality, what has to be considered is how the morality is in fact made up and not how in the opinion of rational philosophers it ought to be made up.” Mewett, loc. cit., (1961-62), 14 U. of T.L.J. 213, at p. 223.

the individual. Moreover, experience teaches us that solutions to particular problems often are the result of compromises on the part of individuals and groups, thus making it still more difficult to rationalize the rules of common morality.

It is not so certain that the evil of punishment, or even the threat of punishment, is actually producing the desired social good, so that in those cases where legal enforcement of morals is not even effec- tively possible, the law should not be allowed to intervene in the field of morality. 10 7 Moreover, punishment has never, as suggested by Hart, resulted in “freezing” morality;1o8 society has, in many in- stances, been able to resist punishment and create pressures so that the law would be changed. In some cases, the very fact of punish- ment or the severity of sanctions has constituted a factor that in- fluenced the amendment or repeal of certain laws. Abuses flowing as a result of undue or unjustified punishment are quite numerous; the most famous are those which followed prohibition laws in the United States, where disorder, violence, defiance of the law and health hazards accompanied bootlegging and other practices by the underworld. The laws on abortion have rendered still more dangerous the extremely numerous cases of illegal abortions, because they are performed by the unskilled under unsafe conditions; here again, the law did not reach its original purpose. 0 9 Of course, punishment is understood in the widest sense possible, but it traditionally refers

107 “Discussion among law-makers, both professional and amateur, is too often limited to what is right or wrong and good or bad for society. There is a failure to keep separate the two questions I have earlier posed – the question of society’s right to pass a moral judgment and the question of whether the arm of the law should be used to enforce the judgment. The criminal law is not a statement of how people ought to behave; it is a statement of what will happen to them if they do not behave.” Devlin, op. cit., p. 20;

“The punishment for grave crimes should adequately reflect the revulsion felt by the majority of citizens for them. It is a mistake to consider the object of punishment as being deterrent or reformative or preventive and nothing else. The ultimate justification of any punishment is not that it is a deterrent but that it is the emphatic denunciation by the community of a crime.. .” Lord Denning, before the Royal Commission on Capital Punishment, cited and criti- cised by Hart, op. cit., p. 65. See supra, nn. 59 and 75, and the text.

108 See Hart, op. cit., p. 72; also Devlin, op. cit., p. 115: “There is no phased programme, no planners to say that if free love is let in in the 60’s, the homo- sexualist must wait until the 70’s.”

109 Facts on homosexuality, prostitution, drug addiction prove it; yet, our society insists that every person who has been convicted once must have a criminal record that will stain its reputation for life. Universities go farther by asking their applicants if they have ever been arrested, although they may have never been convicted. See Mewett, loc. cit., (1961-62), 14 U. of T. L.J. 213, at p. 227.

to methods of individual coercion. Prisons, for example, have been used to a greater extent in the very last centuries, and are under close study as a result of doubts arising out of their usefulness. Modern psychology and medicine have opened the way to better and more positive ways of punishment and rehabilitation, although the preventive sentence imposed to Klippert is perhaps one of the worst examples of modern therapy. Punishment should be seen as the best available instrument to ensure the security of society, the preven- tion of further offences, and the well being and rehabilitation of those who have gone morally astray. Here again, however, the ideas of justice and equality would have to be examined in order to pro- vide some satisfactory conclusion.

There seems to always be those who will claim that where there is evil, there should be punishment, enforceable or not;11 the idea of evil also has to be defined, as has been seen. Kings and bishops have had their mistresses and mignons at times when sexual morality was not in the least relaxed and when theft was punishable by death. There still is a long way to go before morals, society and law can be reconciled into a fully rational and yet equitable system.

Judges and legislators do not really need guidance or philo- sophical guidelines; circumstances and social groups will evidence the common morality and the shift in tolerance. The rest can only be classified as theories. All are as good or bad as the others, that is, insofar as it is impossible to appreciate their relative moral value. However, their internal consistency and their relationship to human behaviour enable the student to illuminate his choice between alter- native ideals of life. On the other hand, precedents show us some good and bad uses of social and legal powers, and some good and bad uses of legal theories. The main difference between insurrection and revolution is success, showing how social order and morality can easily and dangerously become a matter of timing and expert valuation of anticipated shifts in toleration, and reflecting the fun- damental concern of man for freedom and security. 1 “What the law maker has to ascertain is not the true belief but the common belief.”112

11o See supra, Stephen and Hart, op cit., pp. 48 ff. “”‘Freedom, equality, security of life and possessions, and security against certain hazards of human existence must be harmonized in such a way as to bring about a maximum of individual self-realization within the framework of the common goals of humanity.” Bodenheimer, E., Treatise on Justice, (New York, 1.967), pp. 103-104.

112 Devlin, op. cit., p. 94. The author would not be caught saying that there is no true belief. It may, however, be right to say that the common belief is that there is no true belief.

Thank you to our sponsors

the law should enforce morality essay

Advertisement

Advertisement

Enforcing Morality

  • Original Paper
  • Published: 09 June 2013
  • Volume 7 , pages 455–471, ( 2013 )

Cite this article

  • Steven Wall 1  

2023 Accesses

3 Citations

Explore all metrics

In debating Patrick Devlin, H. L. A. Hart claimed that the “modern form” of the debate over the legal enforcement of morals centered on the “significance to be attached to the historical fact that certain conduct, no matter what, is prohibited by a positive morality.” This form of the debate was politically important in 1963 in Britain and America, and it remains politically important in these countries today and elsewhere; but it is not the philosophically most interesting form the debate can take. An older form of the debate appealed to natural law or critical morality. It centered on the question of whether political authorities could properly use the criminal law to enforce critical morality, including prohibitions on conduct that was not harmful or disrespectful to others. This paper engages with this older form of the debate. It offers some reasons for thinking that there is a presumption in favor of the view that it is a proper function of the criminal law to enforce critical morality, including that part of critical morality that is not directly concerned with preventing harm or disrespect to others. It then defends this presumption against some arguments recently pressed by Ronald Dworkin.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

the law should enforce morality essay

Justifying Limitations on the Freedom of Expression

Gehan Gunatilleke

Moral Courage: A Sociological Perspective

Social justice and sociological theory.

Bradley Campbell

H.L.A. Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality (Stanford University Press, 1963). Devlin’s contributions to the debate are collected in his The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford University Press, 1965). In large measure, the debate between Hart and Devlin was provoked by the 1957 “Wolfenden Report” commissioned by the British government on “Homosexual Offenses and Prostitution.”

Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality , pp. 23–24.

For a recent contribution to the debate in this vein see R. George, Making Men Moral (Oxford University Press, 1993).

The existence of critical morality can be rejected, of course. Various relativistic views of morality will find no place for it. This paper is premised on the falsity of such views.

Henceforth, when I speak of Hart or Devlin’s side in the enforcement debate, I mean to refer to opposing views on the proper legal enforcement of critical morality.

Generally, I will use the terms “legitimate” and “permissible” interchangeably. When I have moral requirements in mind, I will speak of moral duties.

Naturally, many will deny that any objects or activities are excellent in this sense. These people can still consider the implications these objects would have for the enforcement of critical morality on the assumption that they have the value here attributed to them.

See, for example, A. Ripstein, Force and Freedom (Harvard University Press, 2009).

Raz suggests, for example, that some forms of injury, such as the infliction of pain, may not diminish a person’s prospects or adversely affect his options, but they are still often regarded as harms. See The Morality of Freedom (Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 413–414.

Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality , pp. 32–33.

J. Feinberg, Harm to Self , p. 16.

To avoid misunderstanding, by “defective will” I mean a will that is not sufficiently voluntary or autonomous. The voluntariness-reducing factors catalogued by Feinberg all point to defects of the will in this sense. See Feinberg, Harm to Self , pp. 150–153.

Living well is sometimes identified with moral rectitude. But this is not how I understand the idea. On my understanding, the moral saint may fail to live well. Living well requires one to lead a good life, and the best life is not identified with either the life highest in well-being or the most virtuous life.

For a statement of this principle see Raz, The Morality of Freedom , p. 194.

The discussion of “authenticity” below engages with some of the concerns that motivate the autonomy objection to legal moralism. But a full consideration of this objection will not be undertaken here.

Might it be a proper function of the criminal law to protect, but never to promote, the well-being of those subject to it? It might be said that, from the standpoint of the law, there is reason to prevent people from falling below a baseline level of well-being, but no corresponding reason to raise their well-being above the baseline level. I doubt that this view could be sustained, however. We would need some way to specify the baseline level of well-being that was determined independently of the law and the criminal law, and it is not at all clear how this could be done in a compelling way. Hence, I speak here both of protecting and promoting well-being.

T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Harvard University Press, 1998), p. 119. The claims in this paragraph and next are indebted to Scanlon’s discussion of well-being and its limits. See especially pp. 126–143.

How is this possible? If succeeding in a rational aim advances a person’s well-being, then how could a person know that to succeed in the aim he must sacrifice his well-being to some extent? The answer is that, while the success of the aim will advance the person’s well-being in virtue of the fact that success in one’s rational aims contributes to well-being, it also may impose costs on the person and these costs could exceed the well-being gains that accrue from succeeding in the aim. In short, the person’s well-being is advanced along one dimension, but diminished more significantly along others.

J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1999 edition), p. 386.

Rawls claimed further that self-respect rests on confidence in one’s ability to successfully carry out one’s plans and intentions, as set by one’s conception of the good. Ibid., p. 386. However, it is less plausible to hold that this kind of self-confidence is necessary to living well. Despite having low confidence in one’s ability, a person may have worthy plans and she may succeed in them despite her lack of confidence in her ability to do so. Such a person could live well.

The attitude of self-respect can be distinguished from the value of self-respect. The former is judgment-dependent. The latter is fact-dependent. I have claimed that if one has the attitude of self-respect, then one will accept that its value is fact-dependent, although I have allowed that, consistent with the attitude of self-respect, one might think that deluded self-respect, while less valuable than nondeluded self-respect, remains valuable to some degree.

A person with good character would be disposed to respect excellence. But it does not follow from this that a person who was disposed to respect excellence, and who responded well to the impersonal reasons grounded by the value of excellent natural and cultural objects, would have a good character. Such a person might have many of the moral and prudential vices associated with bad character, but still respond very well to the reasons of excellence. And it is possible—think here of William’s discussion of Gauguin—that such a person could successfully pursue a sound conception of the good, one oriented toward the achievement of excellence. If so, then the link between having a good character and pursuing a sound conception of the good would be tight, but not water-tight tight.

For example, the kind of case mentioned in the previous note.

See my “Moral Environmentalism” in Paternalism: Theory and Practice , eds. C. Coons and M. Weber (Cambridge University Press, 2013).

R. Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs (Harvard University Press, 2011), p. 212.

Ibid., p. 209.

Dworkin rejects this kind of balancing, but his reasons for doing so are obscure. For criticism of Dworkin on this point, see R. Arneson, “Cracked Foundations of Liberal Equality” in Dworkin and his Critics , ed. J. Burley (Blackwell, 2004).

For Dworkin morality refers to how we ought to treat others, while ethics refers to how we ought to live ourselves. I do not myself accept this way of drawing the distinction, but I need to employ it here to articulate Dworkin’s argument.

There is a gap between defending a moral permission to use the criminal law for a certain purpose and defending the claim that there is a moral duty to do so. But often, if there is no moral duty to do so, then there will be no moral permission to do so either. The reason for this is that the use of the criminal law is a grave matter. To justify its permissible use, the moral considerations for using it must be compelling; and when these considerations are strong enough to justify a moral permission they often will be strong enough to justify a moral requirement.

R. Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 273.

Curiously, this is a point that Dworkin himself appeals to in defending the state’s role in funding the arts. See ibid., p. 274.

Criminal sanctions can stigmatize offenders and impose hard treatment on them. For this reason, some who are otherwise sympathetic to legal moralism may insist that soulcraft should never be pursued by the criminal law. Politics, they will grant, is properly concerned with soulcraft, but they will insist that we cannot help people live well by threatening or punishing them. Yet the case for legal moralism looks not only to the effects of sanctions on the offenders, but also to the wider effects on the ethical environment of the society in which it is undertaken. Even if the criminalization of a targeted activity would not help those who were prosecuted to live better lives, it might be justified all things considered because it would be effective in dissuading others from taking up pursuits that would ruin or mar their lives. On this point see P. Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals , p. 110.

Compare these remarks with the similar view expressed by G. Sher, Beyond Neutrality (Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 70–71.

An in-practice ban on soulcraft could be the prudent thing to do in some circumstances. Principles can be distinguished from what we might call general policies. The former apply to a very wide range of circumstances. By contrast, the latter are tailored to a more specific set of circumstances. General policies could exclude a whole category of state action, such as soulcraft, on the grounds that doing so, in the specified set of circumstances, would be the best response in light of all the relevant values. Nothing I have said in this paper implies that there could not be sound general policies that exclude soulcraft in some circumstances.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Philosophy, The University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ, 85721, USA

Steven Wall

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Wall .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Wall, S. Enforcing Morality. Criminal Law, Philosophy 7 , 455–471 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9238-5

Download citation

Published : 09 June 2013

Issue Date : October 2013

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9238-5

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Self-respect
  • Authenticity
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

Law Explorer

Fastest law search engine.

If you have any question you can ask below or enter what you are looking for!

  • Law Explorer /
  • GENERAL LAW /

Enforcing Morality

31 ENFORCING MORALITY A. P. Simester Introduction Suppose that we are considering whether an action is immoral. Its harmfulness is sometimes, but not always, our starting point. Some actions, such as murder and attempted murder, are wrongs because of the harm to which they conduce. Others are not. Actions such as rape, perjury and blackmail are wrongs prior to any consequences they cause. Their wrongfulness originates elsewhere. It may spring from the means by which the agent does something: not in where you go, as it were, but in how you get there—notably, how you treat people along the way. (Did you deceive her?) In special cases, it may be motive-based, resting on why a person does something. (Was it a warning or threat? An offer or blackmail?) These kinds of action involve what might be termed nonderivative wrongs, in as much as their basic wrongfulness is not dependent upon an outcome. If asked, “Which comes first, the wrong or the harm?” We can only say: it depends. When deciding whether to prohibit such actions, however, a parallel question may not receive the same reply. Famously, for Mill (1859 ch. 1), “the only purpose for which power can rightfully be exercised over any member of a civilised community against his will is to prevent harm to others.” Perhaps, like Feinberg (1984: 34–36), we might require that the harm also be wrongful, but part of the point of the Harm Principle is to focus attention on the harm—and to reject immorality, or wrongfulness per se , as a ground of prohibition. On the other hand, Patrick Devlin (1965: 12–13) controversially asserted that “it is not possible to set theoretical limits to the power of the State to legislate against immorality ⋯ or to define inflexibly areas of morality into which the law is in no circumstances allowed to enter.” Indeed, according to a school of thought known as Legal Moralism, an action can warrant proscription simply on the ground of its moral wrongfulness. Ultimately, these approaches are incompatible. But they share common ground, and Devlin’s challenge helpfully focuses our attention on the requirements of the Harm Principle itself. There is nothing special, or objectionable, about confining prohibitions to morally wrongful actions, i.e., actions that one ought not to do. Those are exactly the sorts of action that prohibitions should address. As we shall see, it is certainly arguable that there are harm-based constraints on state intervention to regulate wrongs. If so, however, they complement rather than displace the wrongfulness requirement. Indeed, a concentration on harm may divert attention from the more general inquiry whether, and if ever when, we should prohibit wrongful conduct. What Counts as Immoral? Depending on one’s views about the scope of morality, it is possible to narrow the gap. Michael Moore (1997: 662), for example, rejects the thought that morality has anything to say about consensual sexual practices. Hence, even on his retributivist view, the state has no basis to criminalize such activities. More generally, if one thinks of morality as an antidote to selfishness (cf. Mackie 1977, ch. 5), reasons may be “moral” ones when they address how we should treat each other. On that view, the legal moralist’s claim to enforce morality will tend to converge with the Harm Principle’s focus on conduct that, directly or indirectly, affects other people’s lives. But that would artificially truncate our inquiry. Devlin’s skepticism about limiting state enforcement of morality finds its strongest expression if we take it that an action is “immoral” whenever it is morally wrongful; and that it is morally wrongful whenever, all things considered, one ought not to do it. In turn, one ought not to do an action whenever the reasons favoring its performance are, all things considered, defeated by the reasons against. For an action to be immoral, therefore, does not require that it is seriously or profoundly wrong, that it be evil or wicked; only that it should not be done. Most wrongful conduct is venial. On this view, practical morality is concerned not merely with how one should treat others but with the question, what should one do? Thus no categorical distinction is drawn here between “moral” and other kinds of reasons, such as prudential ones. There are, of course, many distinctions that we can draw, in particular between guiding reasons (which in fact apply to an action—Raz 1990: 16ff) and explanatory reasons (by which the agent is, subjectively, motivated). The present essay is concerned with guiding reasons—that is, with the reasons why we ought, or ought not, to do something. Yet within that realm, reasons, whether prudential, altruistic or of some other character, are either good—i.e., valid—reasons for doing something, or they are not. Those narrower labels are meaningful, but they are not foundational to the moral question, what ought one to do? Obviously, different kinds of reasons may have differing weights and priorities; what we tend to call “moral” reasons, especially concerning the interests of others, often have relatively greater importance. Yet a reason that is, say, prudential in character can still be a good reason for doing something. Imprudence can be a vice too. Imagine the case of a successful, patriotic businessman, who decides to kill himself should the UK do badly in the next Eurovision Song Contest. He may justly be criticized morally by his friends for resolving to “throw away” his life on such a foolish basis. We do need, however, to distinguish an action’s wrongfulness, or immorality, from its being a wrong . In the usage I adopt here, an action is a wrong when it breaches a duty or violates a right. On occasion, it may be permissible—not wrongful—to perpetrate a wrong, as when D breaks into V’s house in order to call an ambulance to the accident on the road outside. Our main concern in this essay is with the converse issue: whether, as Jeremy Waldron (1981) would put it, one has a right to act wrongfully. Three Theses Concerning Immorality Taking moral wrongfulness as a starting point may seem counterintuitive. It is often said that the law should not be in the business of prohibiting immoral behavior, and at least one version of that claim is surely right. But we need to be careful about what is meant by the claim, and about how convincing it really is. Clarification is required. Here are three possible interpretations: 1. That φing is immoral is insufficient to justify its criminalization (Insufficiency Thesis). 2. That φing is immoral is necessary to justify its criminalization (Necessity Thesis). 3. That φing is immoral is insufficient to establish even a pro tanto ground for its criminalization (Non-qualifying Thesis). (For convenience, I will focus primarily on enforcement through criminal law. As we see below, however, similar principles apply to coercion through the civil law.) The first thesis, that moral wrongfulness is insufficient to justify criminalization, seems uncontroversial. Even Devlin could embrace it. Suppose that φing ought not to be done. Accept too, for the moment, that this generates a reason to prohibit it. It does not follow that, all things considered , we should prohibit φing, because the reason favoring prohibition may be defeated by other considerations. One set of counter-considerations is operational. Even if a prima facie case can be made for prohibition, and φing lies within the range of conduct that there is reason to criminalize, that case must still overcome various negative constraints that militate against criminalization generally. At the very least, to make an all things-considered case for criminalization, we need to show that the criminal law offers an appropriate method of controlling φing, and is preferable to other methods of legal regulation available to the state. Recall the disastrous attempt by many western governments in the twentieth century to regulate alcohol using criminal prohibitions, which created a black market ripe for extortion and racketeering. Rightly, alcohol licensing and taxation laws are now preferred. Other constraints include the practical challenges of crafting an offense definition in terms that are effective, enforceable and which meet rule of law and other concerns (Simester and Sullivan 2007, § 16.5–7). It may be, if these demands cannot be met, that the state ought not to prohibit φing despite the prima facie case for doing so. The in-principle case must also be weighed up against the burdens of prohibition itself, most notably in terms of freedom and lost opportunities (Feinberg 1984: 216). No doubt extramarital affairs constitute wrongful betrayals. But perhaps they should not be criminalized because of the extensive intrusions that their prohibition would involve. For all of these reasons, we should concede the Insufficiency Thesis. But we can do so without concern. For it is a long step from that thesis to concluding (i) that immorality is unnecessary to justify criminalization, or (ii) that even an in-principle case for criminalizing φing requires more than that φing is immoral. The Need for Moral Wrongfulness A very long step. Indeed, conclusion (i) would be a misstep, because the truth is the other way around. Preventing immorality is an indispensable condition of criminalization. It is the Necessity Thesis, not an “un-necessity” thesis, to which we should subscribe: any prohibition of φing can be justified only when φing is morally wrongful action. Within the criminal sphere, the Necessity Thesis is most easily defended by reference to the distinctive nature of criminal law, which punishes, and censures, the offender for having done wrong. The criminal law is a blaming institution, and one cannot blame a person unless that person does something morally wrong; that is, unless she does something that, all things considered, she ought not to do. One can, of course, also judge people morally for their good deeds: yet such judgments are not blaming judgments. Blame lies only for conduct that, all things considered, one should not do. As it happens, while that argument is adequate for the criminal law, a version of the Necessity Thesis holds also for the civil law; and, indeed, for all of us. No moral agent should act wrongfully. And the state is, like the rest of us, subject to the requirements of morality. It too should act in accordance with undefeated, all things-considered reasons. Where it fails to do so, it acts wrongly, just like the rest of us. This matters because if, all things considered, D has undefeated reason to φ, it generally follows that no one, including the state, should stop D from φing. Notwithstanding that D’s reasons to φ may be personal to D, the existence of those reasons is itself a general matter (cf. Gardner 2007: 131). That D has reason to φ, therefore, is something that commands our allegiance too. This is not so much because D herself is entitled to respect—since respect for another human being does not imply that we must always respect the reasons for which that person acts. Rather, it is because the reasons themselves are entitled to respect—that is, because they are (good) reasons. (In passing, we should allow some provisos to this claim. On occasion, the existence of reasons may depend on the status of the agent; thus it is possible that some reasons for individuals to φ may be excluded in the hands of certain other agents, such as the state, and vice versa. More on this possibility later. Neither do I suggest that we should all care just as much about reasons that are personal to others as we should about those personal to us.) Legally Created Wrongs? But what about regulatory laws? It is a commonplace that the state frequently prohibits conduct that is not pre-legally wrong. Indeed such offenses, which Anglo-American lawyers call mala prohibita , form the major part of the criminal canon. They vastly outnumber mala in se proscriptions of conduct that is pre-legally wrong. Yet, if φing is not morally wrongful, how can we justify its prohibition and subsequent punishment? Is the Necessity Thesis incompatible with mala prohibita offenses? This worry has concerned many writers. As Douglas Husak (2007: 112) complains, “I fail to understand why persons behave wrongfully when their conduct is malum prohibitum but not malum in se .” While accepting that some mala prohibita prohibitions may give substantive content to underlying, preexisting wrongs, Husak doubts that many modern offenses do specify such pre-legal wrongs. This line of thought is partly right and partly misleading. It is right in so far as it reflects the truth—and it is a truth—that φing does not become morally wrong just because the state declares it so. But it is misleading in that it doesn’t sufficiently distinguish prohibition, which is forward looking, from punishment, which is retrospective and ex post . The justification of an act of criminalization is not the same as the justification of an act of punishment. They are different acts. The former can play a role in justifying the latter. How so? Because the state sometimes creates specific moral reasons. Moreover, it can do so in a variety of ways (e.g., Honoré1993; Finnis 1980: 284ff). Indeed, that power is not restricted to the state. When the soccer referee shows a player a red card, the player thereupon has a reason, indeed a duty, to leave the pitch. Any moral agent in a position of authority can create reasons: the power to do so is part of the very idea of authority (cf. Raz 1979, ch. 1). Prior to law, there is no reason to drive on any particular side of the road, but one arises as soon as the state stipulates on which side the citizens should drive. If the state rules that we must drive on the right, it thereby creates a post-legal reason so to do. Admittedly, this involves a contingency: that the authority is not merely legitimate but effective, so that there is a reasonable expectation of conformity with the rules it creates. But this does not seem too much to require, since effectiveness is a general condition of the instrumental reasons underpinning a state’s authority. In one sense, the law’s role here is to generate authoritative conventions. At the same time, the rule is not mere convention. Imagine that (as sometimes occurs in certain countries) one arrives at a road being unsure what is the local driving practice. One knows the legal rule—drive on the left, say—but not whether it is observed. Other things being equal, one should drive on the left. Slowly. Many standard examples of successful norm creation involve conventions, typically as coordinating rules or as content-determinations of some more abstract, pre-conventional norm. How many players to field on a soccer team? How should we return the ball into play? What side to drive on? Th answers to these questions may be to some extent arbitrary, even suboptimal; yet the very existence of an authoritative answer is itself valuable. Now we can have an organized game. Now we can drive with more safety. And so on. The precise content of these coordinating rules may be less important than the purpose they serve. Even a rule about the age of consent in underage sexual intercourse, which most people would regard as a mala in se offense, is partially conventional. It varies widely across jurisdictions and history. But the rule is valuable—morally valuable—in virtue of helping to articulate one boundary of permissible sexual activity, benefiting potential offenders as well as potential victims by its clarity. In all these kinds of cases, the state has good ex ante reason for passing the relevant law. In effect, the state acts as a conduit, crystallizing those ex ante reasons into a more particular, practicable form—the moral force of which derives not from the enactment itself, but from its function. Generally speaking, the wrongfulness of a rule violation depends on the moral force of the rule. For a malum prohibitum rule, the moral force comes from its instrumental value, which depends, in turn, on the reasons the rule serves and how well it serves them.

IMAGES

  1. A Level Law: Law and Justice Essay // Law and Morality Essay

    the law should enforce morality essay

  2. Law and Morality Essay

    the law should enforce morality essay

  3. How To Write A Law Essay Like A Pro

    the law should enforce morality essay

  4. (PDF) LAW AND MORALITY

    the law should enforce morality essay

  5. It is immoral to enforce morality as law. Discuss Essay

    the law should enforce morality essay

  6. law and morality essay a level law ocr

    the law should enforce morality essay

COMMENTS

  1. PDF Candidate Style Answers LAW

    the problems of trying to make the law enforce morality in a pluarlist society. Good terminology is used and there are examples in the answer. Examples can come from the 'whole course of study' and this student has used examples from the Law Making, Crime and Tort units. The Hart-Devlin debate is a well-known aspect of a morality essay.

  2. Should There Be Morality in the Law?

    H.L.A Hart: Within Hart's theory, he maintains that Law and Morality should remain separate. In one of his most famous works; 'The Concept of Law [1] ' he analysis' the relation between that is between law, coercion and morality. In order to try to and clarify whether laws are coercive orders or moral commands.

  3. Law Enforce Morality: Analysis Essay Sample

    Ashworth suggests (2009, p.23ff) that we are morally responsible because of said individual autonomy. But this seems contrary to reality; indeed, it is precisely for the benefit of autonomy that we ought not have responsibilities. States are robber bands enlarged, for there is no justice in controlling others; punishment is a cruel and ...

  4. The Hart-Devlin Debate: Should Law Be Used to Enforce Morality?

    Abstract. This work investigates the famous law and morality debate between Hart and Devlin. It discusses the crucial question of whether the law should be used to enforce morality? It examines how the issue was started by J. S. Mill and how it was responded to by James Stephen; how the debate resurfaced in the middle of the 20th century with ...

  5. Legal Enforcement of Morality

    Abstract. "Legal Enforcement of Morality" addresses the question how far the law should enforce what people morally should do. Clearly the law should forbid many acts that harm others, but not every moral harm, such as hurt feelings. Sometimes the law should require acts that benefit others. The failure of our laws to require a stranger to ...

  6. PDF Law versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct

    The enforcement of law will refer to three stages. The first is the iden-tification and reporting of violators to the state. This might be done by pri-vate parties who bring suits for violations or by public enforcement agents, for example, safety inspectors or police officers. Second, law enforcement requires adjudication.

  7. Should Law reflect morality? (very short answer for 40 mark essay

    Devlin believed that society is itself constituted by morality, meaning society has a right to protect itself against immoral conduct, meaning that Devlin believed that the law should fully reflect morality. However he did recognise limits to this, stating that the law should only reflect morality where the reasonable man would see a potential ...

  8. Legal Enforcement of Morality

    LEGAL ENFORCEMENT OF MORALITY. 723. garding morality, while respecting wide variations in private life, just as communities now respect wide variations in religious belief and practice. 18 Neither position is illogical. The real issue is a factual one, and the answer could vary from community to community.

  9. The Legal Enforcement of Morality

    There may be conceivable legal systems that contain no such authorization (Raz 1975: 158-160). But enforceable legal norms form part of every legal system we know to have existed. And in every such system, those norms impose duties that form part of morality, including duties not to kill, maim, cheat, or steal from others (Hart 1961: 192ff).

  10. The authority of law: Essays on law and morality

    Abstract. This revised edition of one of the classic works of modern legal philosophy, first published in 1979, represents the author's contribution which has had an enduring influence on philosophical work on the nature of law and its relation to morality. The new edition includes two previously uncollected essays and a new introduction from ...

  11. PDF Should Law Improve Morality?

    Abstract Lawyers and philosophers have long debated whether law should enforce social morality. This paper explores whether law should improve social morality. It explains how this might be possible, and what sort of obstacles, factual and moral, there are to doing so. It concludes with an example: our law should attempt to improve our social

  12. Law and Morality Essay

    Law and Morality Essay. Discussion about law and morality and their interdependence. Module. Opinion Writing. 24 Documents. Students shared 24 documents in this course. ... In conclusion, law should reflect the prevailing moral standards in society, but it cannot depend wholly on them, it should be a clear distinction between legal and moral ...

  13. Law Should Be Kept Separate From Morality Law Essay

    The statement quoted from the Wolfenden Report suggests that there should remain a line between sin and crime and that the law should not interfere in matters of private morality or immorality keeping it apart from public morality. This is a broad view and clearly, there are some areas in which the law should act as a moral guardian and ...

  14. Lord Devlin and the Enforcement of Morals

    75:986. the vast bulk of a community thinks a practice is immoral they are likely right. What Lord Devlin thinks is at stake, when our public morality is challenged, is the very survival of society, and he believes that society is entitled to preserve itself without vouching for the morality that holds it together.

  15. Does Law Exist to Provide Moral Order?

    On the other hand, laws against dangerous driving (or, say, murder), for example, are no doubt influenced by morality, but they are also part of social-bureaucratic order. And well-ordered states are not necessarily moral states. Devlin's claim that laws are there to enforce morality was, Hart pointed out, simply factually incorrect.

  16. The Legal Enforcement of Morals and the So-Called Hart-Devlin

    42 In his most recent essay on the legal enforcement of morals ((1967), 35 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 1), Hart proposes a distinction between the 'classical thesis', ... of the law is to enforce morality, that is, morality adopted for the time being by the "party"; regulations affecting hygiene and sexual morality in state residences and ...

  17. Introduction (Chapter 1)

    Legal systems enforce morality. No one really denies it. "It cannot be seriously disputed," H. L. A. Hart observes, "that the development of law, at all times and places, has in fact been profoundly influenced both by the conventional morality and ideals of particular social groups, and also by forms of enlightened moral criticism urged by individuals, whose moral horizon has transcended ...

  18. The Concept, the Idea, and The Morality of Law an Essay in

    This may be the case in Austria and the U.S.A. On the other hand LAW conceived in terms of morality can find no place for a positivist or morally neutral LAW-IDEA. For in this case an immoral "law" would be not merely, as in the former case, invalid within the system, but a contradiction in terms throughout the writer's Jurisprudence.

  19. Should Law Improve Morality?

    Lawyers and philosophers have long debated whether law should enforce social morality. This paper explores whether law should improve social morality. It explains how this might be possible, and what sort of obstacles, factual and moral, there are to doing so. It concludes with an example: our law should attempt to improve our social morality of sexual conduct.

  20. (PDF) An Essay about Law, Freedom, and Morality. Some Chosen and

    PDF | On Apr 19, 2013, Dawid Bunikowski published An Essay about Law, Freedom, and Morality. Some Chosen and Revised Considerations on Aspects of Enforcement of Morality by the Law | Find, read ...

  21. PDF The Enforcement of Morals Revisited Richard J. Arneson (Final version

    2. The legal enforcement of morality as such. Hart opposes and Devlin supports the legal enforcement of morals as such. Hart understands the issue in terms of a contrast he draws between positive and critical morality.6 The positive morality of a society is the moral code that is actually embraced and upheld by the generality of its members.

  22. Enforcing Morality

    The Presumption can be articulated by identifying the theses it commits us to. Start with autonomy. E 1: It is a proper function of the criminal law to enforce respect for the autonomy of persons. Critical morality, I am assuming, includes respect for autonomy and so those who accept the Presumption should grant E 1.

  23. Enforcing Morality

    Devlin's skepticism about limiting state enforcement of morality finds its strongest expression if we take it that an action is "immoral" whenever it is morally wrongful; and that it is morally wrongful whenever, all things considered, one ought not to do it. In turn, one ought not to do an action whenever the reasons favoring its ...